In this paper, I develop a methodological challenge for ethical
nonnaturalism. The challenge is methodological because it concerns the
way many nonnaturalists argue for their views. I suggest that there is
an overlooked problem for a central and prevalent positive argument for
nonnaturalism, the argument from ethical phenomenology. This
problem, I intend to show, ultimately renders nonnaturalism
indefensible—at least in so far as the view is solely based on this
argument.
Let us start by clarifying the goals of metaethical theorizing. Here
is a useful characterization:
That is, metaethics
concerns the nature of moral thought, moral language, moral facts, moral
properties, and moral knowledge.
Nonnaturalists believe that ethical thought and talk involves
nonnatural entities. What does that mean? Nonnatural
entities are thought to be categorically distinct from, or “something
over and above,” the natural. Nonnaturalists typically
do not claim that all ethical entities are nonnatural. Some
ethical entities are “mixed”; they consist of a combination of natural
and nonnatural entities. (For example, the fact that Anna’s hitting Ben
is wrong consists of a natural part—the hitting—and a non-natural
part—the hitting’s wrongness.) But, crucially, nonnaturalists claim that
the most fundamental ethical entities are “purely” nonnatural
(cf. Scanlon 2014,
36–37). In this sense, they are categorically distinct from, or
something over and above, natural entities.
Why believe that ethical entities are nonnatural? One prevalent
nonnaturalist argument—the argument from ethical phenomenology—takes the
form of an inference to the best explanation and consists of two steps:
First, describe the phenomenology of ethical deliberation. Second, show
that the best explanation for it—the best explanation for why
this is what ethical deliberation is like—involves the
existence of nonnatural entities.
The typical naturalist response to the argument from ethical
phenomenology is that there are better explanations for the
phenomenology of ethical deliberation than the existence of nonnatural
entities. However, we will pursue a different path here. Our
methodological challenge is logically prior to responses of this kind.
We will try to show, not that there are better explanations, but that,
quite generally, the outlined way of arguing for the existence of
nonnatural entities is methodologically problematic. In short, our
charge will be that it is methodologically unreasonable to explain or
interpret ethical phenomenology by making metaphysical claims without
taking into account another, more “external” perspective on ethical
thought and talk.
Here is our plan. Section 1 introduces two
distinct perspectives on mental processes and argues that both
perspectives are important when it comes to understanding how these
processes fit into reality. Ethical deliberation is a mental process,
and so it will be worth reflecting on how, in general, philosophers
should approach these processes. Based on the insights gathered here,
section 2 introduces the challenge from lost perspective in the context
of David Enoch’s work (Enoch 2011). This section is the heart
of the paper. Section 3 discusses two
nonnaturalist attempts to meet the challenge Parfit (2011). Both attempts involve the
so-called “just too different intuition.” I show why they cannot
succeed. At this point, it will hopefully have become clear that the
argument from ethical phenomenology runs into a serious methodological
problem. It can only get off the ground by presupposing something
opponents of nonnaturalism (whether reductionists, expressivists, or
error-theorists) deny, namely, that the external perspective is
irrelevant for metaethical theorizing. The argument, in other
words, begs the question on a methodological level. The final section sums up our main points and
recommends a strategy to future nonnaturalists.
Reconciling Two Perspectives
As Mark Timmons
(1999) and Terence Cuneo (2007b) have helpfully
emphasized, the metaethical project can be described as a
twofold endeavor. The first part of it is the “internal accommodation
project”: developing a theory of ethical thought and talk that fits well
with “deeply embedded assumptions” of our ordinary ethical thought and
practice (Cuneo 2007b,
854). In other words, the internal accommodation project aims for
the theory that best accounts for our internal perspective on ethics,
our ethical phenomenology. For example, it is (presumably) a deeply
embedded assumption of ethical thought and talk that if an agent has a
moral belief, she is pro tanto motivated to act accordingly. So, a
plausible metaethical
view should account for this feature.
The second part of the metaethical project is the “external
accommodation project.” Its goal is to come up with a metaethical theory that
fits well with the “scientific world view.” For example, a metaethical view should, at
least, not directly contradict scientific insights into human nature as
presented by, say, evolutionary biology or empirical psychology.
Ideally, a metaethical
view would get further evidential support from scientific research such
that we, ultimately, get a unified “phenomenological-cum-scientific”
theory of ethical thought and talk. However, it might also turn out that
the ethical domain is “autonomous,” and that scientific insights are
simply irrelevant when it comes to the fundamental ethical entities. If
so, the external accommodation project would (maybe trivially) be
completed, but more about that later.
These two explanatory projects form the basis of our challenge to
nonnaturalism. In the following, we will
distinguish the internal perspective from the external
perspective. The internal perspective delivers the stuff relevant for
the project of internal accommodation; it grants access to some process
or practice “from within.” The external perspective delivers what is
necessary for the project of external accommodation; it provides
insights into some process or practice “from without,” by means of
investigations that are not phenomenological.
Importantly, I take the external accommodation project to cover more
than just the methods of the natural sciences. What I mean is the a
posteriori investigation of a process or practice that goes beyond
phenomenological observations. For example, an anthropological
investigation of the practice of monetary transactions counts as
external. Such an investigation looks at the practice “from
without,” for instance, by focusing on the societal advantages of trade.
It is based on insights gathered from the external perspective
(and not based on the “phenomenology of money experiences”).
Back to nonnaturalism. Is the idea that there are nonnatural entities
the result of external or internal accommodation? As we are about to see
in the following section, the claim typically
results from an internal accommodation. Nonnaturalists usually
start with ethical phenomenology and then proceed to explain it via
metaphysical hypotheses that involve nonnatural entities.
But, importantly, these hypotheses are not directly “revealed” by
internal, phenomenological analyses. Instead, they are
interpretations of our phenomenology. And these interpretations
are part of the nonnaturalists’ internal accommodation project because
they are solely based on phenomenological appearances.
Now, let us illustrate how both perspectives on mental processes can
be brought together. Take the example of human disgust. We could either
start investigating disgust “from within,” that is, with its
what-it-is-like. This would involve, say, analyzing the stream
of thoughts and feelings present in disgust episodes. Or we could assume
the external perspective and explain, “from without,” what anchors
disgust reactions in the empirical world. This would involve, for
instance, analyzing (neuro)physiological processes and disgust’s
evolutionary function.
Start with the internal perspective. What is it like to encounter
rotten food? You feel a strong inclination or desire not to get too
close to the food. Touching it with your bare skin strikes you as
repulsive. You might experience nausea. You want to get rid of the
rotten food as quickly as possible. And if you imagine having
accidentally put it into your mouth, your reactions further escalate.
Yuck, away with it!
Now, trying to come up with a theory of disgust, you might discover
that there are many other disgusting things. There are greasy, sticky,
or malodorous objects, blood, mutilation, waste, hygiene violations, and
even some animals (e.g., rats, cockroaches, worms, or flies). This can
seem quite puzzling: Why is it that we react to all these
different things in the same way? Do
they have something in common that might explain our reaction to them?
Is there more to find out and understand about disgust than we can
observe from the internal perspective?
Of course there is. But in order to find out more, we need to assume
the external perspective. According to a widely accepted scientific
theory, disgust is a behavioral extension of the immune system (Rozin, Haidt and
McCauley 2008). It helps us to avoid pathogens. Very roughly:
disgust is triggered when we encounter something potentially infectious,
which helps us to avoid it. So, assuming the external perspective on
disgust is quite illuminating. Undoubtedly, our understanding has been
enriched by it. On top of the detailed phenomenological descriptions of
what it is like to experience disgust, we now also understand what
anchors disgust in the world as conceived by the natural sciences. We
have a better grasp of its “point”—of why beings like us are disgusted
in the first place. We also better understand why there are a whole
range of different things that evoke the same disgust reactions. Blood,
greasy objects, and rats are all “signs” for the presence of
pathogens—and thus to be avoided. In a first and preliminary attempt, we
might (partly) characterize disgustingness as something along the lines
of being an indicator of the above-some-threshold likelihood of the
presence of pathogens.
I take it that disgustingness is a good example because of its
evaluative or normative dimension. What renders a
property evaluative? (McDowell 1985, 143–146)
distinguishes non-evaluative properties that “merely” causally influence
our responses from evaluative properties that merit certain
responses. His criterion for assigning a property to the evaluative camp
is “the possibility of criticism” (1985, 144). Now, I think it is
fair to say that a dead rat in one’s fridge merits disgust. If
Fred discovered a dead rat in his fridge and showed no signs of disgust
while happily starting to eat the open bowl of yoghurt that has been
standing right next to the cadaver, we would ask ourselves what is wrong
with him. Thus, I side with McDowell and state that disgustingness has
an evaluative dimension. So, even in the case of properties with an
evaluative or normative dimension, external insights can be quite
resourceful.
The above considerations set the stage for the main claim of the current section:
Methodologically speaking, an investigation of the nature of
any mental process (and the involved entities) should take into
account and try to reconcile both the internal and the external
perspective.
Let me elaborate. Suppose Danielle
wants to investigate the nature of disgust. She only cares for a
phenomenological investigation, and so she never even considers taking
into account what the sciences have to say. Scrutinizing disgust
phenomenology for a few days, she ultimately concludes that
disgustingness is a nonnatural property that human beings can apprehend
via a special, intuition-like faculty. Some otherwise seemingly
unrelated objects (blood and cockroaches, say) instantiate this
property, and somehow the human mind can recognize it. Note that nothing
in the phenomenology of disgust speaks against Danielle’s disgust nonnaturalism; her view
accounts (we may assume) for all the relevant phenomenological data
quite well. But now suppose that Danielle’s
friend Fatima decides to tell her all the scientific insights about
human disgust reactions. She tells her that disgust tracks possible
sources of infection and that scientists consider this tracking function
as its evolutionary point. Now, here is a crucial question: Coming to
learn all the external facts about human disgust reactions, should Danielle’s confidence in disgust nonnaturalism
change?
I believe that, upon learning the external facts, it would be
rational for Danielle to change her
confidence in disgust nonnaturalism. These newly learned facts
suggest—and this is a crucial step in my argument—that disgustingness is
closely metaphysically linked to something quite natural: the
likely presence of pathogens. It is due to this suggested metaphysical
link that Danielle should take her disgust
nonnaturalism to be less plausible than before.
Coming to know the external evidence, it is rational for Danielle to decrease her confidence in
the idea that disgustingness is something categorically distinct,
something “over and above,” the natural. It must now seem more
likely to her that disgustingness fits into reality by being a
natural property. (Note that Danielle now
understands why blood and cockroaches instantiate
disgustingness.) Consequently, she should decrease her confidence in the
idea that disgustingness is a nonnatural property.
Based on these considerations, we may formulate a (not entirely
catchy) slogan: External evidence can shift the plausibility of
metaphysical explanations of the phenomenology of mental processes.
As we just saw, the external perspective on human disgust reactions
influences the plausibility of Danielle’s
disgust nonnaturalism. In virtue of plausibility shifts of this kind, it
is methodologically unreasonable to draw metaphysical conclusions about
the nature of disgustingness on solely phenomenological
grounds. If we want to find out how any mental process fits into the
reality that the empirical sciences have taught us so much about, it
would be a bad idea to disregard possibly relevant empirical
evidence.
We may put two points on record. Firstly, the internal and the
external perspectives on disgust complement each other.
Reconciling them helps us “anchor” disgust in the natural world.
Moreover, adding the external perspective to Danielle’s investigation changes the
plausibility of her solely phenomenology-based metaphysical account of
disgustingness. So, if you want to write a book titled “Disgust: What It
Is and How It Fits into Reality” you should take the external
perspective into account. Not doing so would be methodologically
unreasonable.
Secondly, our two perspectives deliver characterizations of disgust
that look very different but are intimately linked. For example, part of
a phenomenological description of disgust is the “yuck”-reaction, a
strong inclination to get rid of the disgusting object. There seems to
be a large gap between this description and the external story, which
includes, besides a list of facts about neurophysiology and muscle
twitches, that disgust is an evolutionary tool for tracking and avoiding
possibly infectious objects. Despite this gap, there is an intimate
connection. Plausibly, the disgustingness of the dead rat in your fridge
(partly) consists in the likelihood of its being a source of infection.
A close metaphysical link between the dead rat’s disgustingness
and some set of scientifically accessible properties can, at least,
not be ruled out.,
These two methodological conclusions, I think, apply to mental
processes more generally. The case of disgust suggests that, whenever we
investigate a mental process, we should take into account both
perspectives on it—unless there is reason to believe that one
perspective is utterly irrelevant for investigating the respective
mental process. As long as we don’t know about such
a reason, we should be open to all the internal and external evidence we
might get hold on—which lets us formulate two methodological guide
lines:
When you interpret or explain the phenomenology of mental
processes (and the involved entities), take into account both the
internal and the external perspective on the respective
processes.
While the internal and the external perspective might describe
mental processes (and the involved entities) in very different ways, do
not take this to rule out that the entities mentioned in both
descriptions are closely metaphysically linked.
In this section, we have argued that an
investigation of the nature of any mental process should take into
account and try to reconcile both the internal and the external
perspective. This will serve as a fruitful ground for our objection to
the argument from ethical phenomenology. As we are going to claim in the
upcoming section, the argument violates our
first methodological guideline; it constructs a moral metaphysics on
phenomenological grounds without taking into account the
external perspective.
The Challenge from Lost
Perspective
Ethical nonnaturalists have a rich history of constructing ethical
ontologies out of phenomenological analyses of ethical deliberation.
They answer the question of how ethical entities fit into reality by
stating that reality comprises more than the sciences would have us
believe. There are, they claim, nonnatural ethical entities. Depending
on what particular view we are dealing with, these entities are truths,
facts, properties, or relations. But whatever they are, the crucial idea
is that they are something categorically distinct from, something over
and above, the natural. Now, let us take a closer look at
one version of the argument from ethical phenomenology.
David Enoch advocates the argument from
the moral implications of objectivity (Enoch 2011, 16–49). It runs as follows:
In cases of preference conflicts—say, about where to have dinner
tonight—it intuitively seems that we should solve the conflict
impartially. It would not be okay to declare that Mark’s preference for
Italian is more important than Anna’s preference for Indian.
Intuitively, they should agree that their preferences count the same,
and then find a solution from here on out. Clearly, none of their
preferences is mistaken. On the other hand, in a moral
conflict, it intuitively seems that the appropriate response is
not impartial. For example, if I disagree with someone claiming
that not a single refugee from Ukraine should be allowed to cross the
German border, she strikes me as mistaken. It seems to me that
my opinion has some objective backing—and that an impartial treatment of
our “moral preferences” would be deeply misguided. So, there is an
internal, phenomenological difference between moral disagreements and
conflicts of preference. The former ones have (or seem to have) an
objectively right answer. The latter ones don’t. And this, according to
Enoch, is “best explained” by a robust nonnaturalist realism ((Enoch 2018, 40); (Enoch 2011,
16–49)).
This argument fits the general pattern of the argument from ethical
phenomenology. Starting with phenomenological observations about the
differences between moral disagreements and conflicts of preference, it
draws a metaphysical conclusion to explain this difference. So, the
argument is a suitable target for our methodological worries.
There are, of course, many other versions of the argument from
ethical phenomenology. However, in the following, I will
mostly rely on considerations from Enoch (2011) because they strike me as
particularly straightforward. I hope it will become clear that my
methodological worries can be extrapolated to different versions of the
argument from ethical phenomenology proposed by other nonnaturalist
authors. Let us turn to these worries now.
Metaethics, we said,
is the project of explaining how ethical thought and talk, and what it
is about, fits into reality. Now, trivially, reality does not exhaust
itself in phenomenology. As the case of disgust served to show, the
phenomenology of a mental process might only be one side of the coin.
Sometimes, there is another side—a side that is only revealed if we look
at the process from the external perspective. Therefore—and in the
absence of reasons to the contrary—we should take into account
both perspectives when trying to understand how a mental
process and the involved truths, facts, properties, or relations fit
into reality. If you want to write a book titled “Ethical Thought and
Talk: What It Is and How It Fits into Reality” and you are not planning
to even look at the subject matter from an external perspective, chances
are you are missing something relevant. This would be methodologically
unreasonable. We already saw how external evidence can shift the
plausibility of metaphysical claims that solely rest on phenomenological
observations. Due to the possibility of such shifts, you should at least
give the external evidence a shot at informing your metaphysics. And so
we may raise the following challenge:
Challenge from Lost
Perspective.
Proponents of the argument from ethical phenomenology must tell
us why the external perspective on ethical thought and talk does not
need to be taken into account before they conclude, on solely
phenomenological grounds, that ethical thought and talk is about
nonnatural entities.
There is a slight chance that nonnaturalists remain unimpressed by
this challenge. They might ask: What could the external perspective
possibly contribute to our understanding of ethics? I have a
quick and a not-so-quick reply. Here’s the quick one: The question of
how ethical thought and talk fit into reality is a descriptive question
about the reality we live in. We already know that there are many truths
about this reality that cannot be discovered by phenomenological
investigations. Therefore, it strikes me as quite commonsensical to at
least entertain the possibility that the external
perspective—which has proven quite resourceful in teaching us about the
nature of reality—has something to contribute here. But since
this answer might be considered too superficial, let me try again and
present my not-so-quick reply.
Suppose we have two different explanations of the phenomenology of
ethical deliberation on the table. One of them is nonnaturalism,
according to which the “currencies” of ethical deliberation—values and
reasons—essentially involve nonnatural entities. The other one is a
broadly “Humean” explanation, according to which values and reasons are
grounded in our conative, desire-like attitudes. They are, as (Finlay 2014,
249–250) nicely puts it, “shadow[s] cast by our desires […].” How
could the external perspective contribute anything to this debate
between the nonnaturalist and the Humean?
Here is one possibility: It might turn out that, from an external
perspective, ethical deliberation is an evolutionarily acquired tool for
“conative mind-management,” that is, for dealing with conflicts between
and hierarchizing our conative attitudes.
As human beings with a capacity for imagination, a limitless time
horizon, deeply entrenched social needs, and thus a multitude of
conflicting attitudes, we face an enormous evolutionary challenge:
managing our minds in order to be coherent agents, and then coordinating
our actions with our fellow community members. Investigating the human
mind from the external perspective of evolutionary anthropology, we
might encounter the hypothesis that ethical deliberation is an
evolutionary, cultural tool for solving this challenge.
Let me be clear: I do not want to argue for this hypothesis. My main
point is conditional, but it suffices to answer the question of what the
external perspective could possibly contribute. If the external
perspective revealed something along these lines, this would (much like
in the case of disgust) shift the plausibility of the nonnaturalist and
the Humean explanations. How? Well, the nonnaturalist explanation would
lose some plausibility points, whereas the Humean explanation would gain
some. Why? Because metaethics is concerned with explaining how
ethical thought and talk fit into reality and because, as argued above,
we should take into account and try to reconcile both perspectives in
this process. If the “external point” of ethical deliberation turned out
to be conative mind-management, this would fit better with a broadly
Humean view, according to which there is a close metaphysical
link between values and reasons on the one hand, and conative
attitudes on the other hand. Since nonnaturalists reject such a link,
their explanation would lose some plausibility points. Additionally,
combining a Humean view with our stipulated external story would promise
a more parsimonious account of how ethical thought and talk fit into
reality. This is how the external
perspective could contribute to the metaethical debate between the nonnaturalist and
the Humean.
The outlined external story about the evolutionary point of ethical
deliberation is, of course, hypothetical. But our general methodological
consideration is not. We argued that external investigations into mental
processes can (and often do) shift the plausibility of (metaphysical)
interpretations of the respective phenomenologies. Thus, we should take
into account the external perspective when developing and assessing
these interpretations. Importantly, this holds even if external evidence
ultimately turns out to be irrelevant for metaethical theorizing.
Even in that case, it would still be true that disregarding the external
perspective would have been methodologically unreasonable; when we
started the investigation, we simply didn’t know.
This means that proponents of the argument from ethical phenomenology
face a problem. They proceed in a methodologically unreasonable way.
They construct a controversial moral metaphysics on phenomenological
grounds without taking into account the external evidence.
Let us put a concrete example on the table. Enoch’s second main
argument for nonnaturalism is the argument from deliberative
indispensability. Like his first
argument, it is a version of the argument from ethical
phenomenology. When introducing it, Enoch explicitly disregards the
external perspective as irrelevant.
Had we been here in the explanatory business – trying to explain
action, or perhaps even deliberation, from a third-person point of view
– perhaps desires would have been enough (though I doubt it). But the
whole point of the argument of this chapter is the focus on the
first-person, deliberative perspective. And from this perspective,
desires are not often relevant, and whether they are or are not, the
normative commitment is – though perhaps implicit – inescapable. […]
[W]e need normative truths even if, viewed from an external perspective,
our desires suffice in order to cause our actions and then explain them,
because, when deliberating, we know our desires are merely our
desires. (Enoch 2011, 76,
footnotes left out)
Interestingly, Enoch seems to agree that there is an external
perspective from which deliberation could be investigated. But then he
dismisses the relevance of possible external insights—desires
could help to explain the nature of deliberation—for the
purposes of his chapter because desires play no important
internal role on the conscious mental stage of deliberation. The whole point of his chapter, he
suggests, is to better understand the nature of normative truths from a
first-person point of view. And, by the end of the chapter, he
concludes that we should best think of these truths as nonnatural. So,
according to what we have said, Enoch’s approach is methodologically
unreasonable; his two main arguments for ethical nonnaturalism construct
a moral metaphysics on phenomenological grounds without taking into
account the external perspective.
To be fair, however, we should mention that Enoch does consider the
external perspective on ethical deliberation later in his book. There, he discusses Sharon Street’s
Darwinian Dilemma for Moral Realism (2006) as an
epistemological challenge to his view. We won’t dive into the details.
For our purposes, it suffices to focus on the way Enoch replies
to Street’s dilemma. First, he reminds us that metaethics is about scoring plausibility points.
Ultimately, he says, metaethicists offer package deals, and the one with
the most plausibility points wins. In this spirit, Enoch preliminarily
remarks that his view does not need to do “better than competing
metanormative theories in every respect, with regard to every
problem” (Enoch
2011, 167). And so he sets out to show that his two positive
arguments for nonnaturalism scored him more points than he was about to
lose due to the epistemological challenge. Ultimately, after having
presented his solution to the challenge, he states: “Let me not give the
impression that this suggested way of coping with the epistemological
challenge is ideal. […] [P]erhaps Robust Realism does lose some
plausibility points here. But not, it seems to me, too many, and
certainly not as many as you may have thought” (2011, 175). So, Enoch believes that his
two main arguments for the existence of nonnatural ethical facts—two
different versions of the argument from ethical phenomenology—generate
such a significant number of plausibility points that later objections
to his view, formulated from an external perspective, can be met via an
inferior solution—because he doesn’t lose as many points as he
previously scored.
I find this rather unconvincing. It will take the rest of this section to explain why.
We argued earlier that, when interpreting or explaining mental
processes, it is methodologically unreasonable to draw metaphysical
conclusions on solely phenomenological grounds. Now, start by noting
that this is precisely what Enoch does when he develops his positive
arguments for nonnaturalism—even if it is true that he
later confronts his metaphysical conclusions with an objection
formulated from the external perspective. For all we said above, the
external evidence regarding the nature of ethical deliberation may have
significantly decreased the plausibility of Enoch’s
metaphysical conclusions—in which case we should never have drawn them
in the first place.
But nonnaturalists might want to object: Does it really matter
when we take into account the external perspective? Enoch
clearly does take it into account, so where is the problem? As long as
we do take it into account at some point, we should be fine,
shouldn’t we? I don’t think so. It actually does matter when we
take into account the external perspective because, as long as we don’t,
we cannot assign plausibility points to our metaphysics.
Without taking into account the external evidence, we simply cannot
know how plausible our solely phenomenology-based metaphysical
explanation is. But this is a complicated thought, so let me elaborate a
little.
As we just saw, Enoch is quite confident that, despite his less than
ideal solution to the epistemological challenge, he “certainly” does not
lose as many points as he previously scored. Let us reconsider his
approach in light of our methodological worries. Enoch first explicitly
disregards a perspective it is, we argued, methodologically unreasonable
to disregard. This allows him to draw his metaphysical conclusions
precisely in the way the way we claimed to be methodologically
unreasonable. Later, Enoch confronts his metaphysical picture with
objections from the perspective that he previously disregarded. Doing
so, he finds that his metaphysical picture, which was drawn, again, in a
methodologically unreasonable way, gained such a high (!) number of
plausibility points that they “certainly” cannot be outweighed by
objections generated by the perspective whose taking into account would
have stopped his conclusions from being methodologically unreasonable in
the first place.
This strikes me as fishy. When we construct a metaphysics on solely
phenomenological grounds, we should expect that, once we add the
external perspective to our investigation, the plausibility of our
metaphysics might change. (Recall Danielle’s disgust nonnaturalism.) But this
means that we cannot—and, importantly, Enoch
cannot—confidently distribute plausibility points to his metaphysics
before weighing in the external evidence. This, I think, is a
crucial implication of our earlier methodological considerations. If
these considerations are correct, if drawing metaphysical conclusions on
solely phenomenological grounds is methodologically unreasonable, then
the plausibility of these conclusions should be considered
uncertain as long as we haven’t weighed in the external
evidence. In other words, our methodological considerations suggest that
the number of plausibility points Enoch’s moral metaphysics scores
itself depends on how well it fits with the external evidence.
Therefore, Enoch’s allocation of any particular number of
plausibility points to his metaphysics—let alone a high number
of points—is unwarranted. Enoch simply cannot know how plausible his
metaphysics is until he has taken the external evidence into account.
Consider an analogous case. Tim wants to
investigate the nature of taste. At the beginning of his investigation,
he explicitly disregards the external perspective. His solely
phenomenological investigation leads him to the conclusion that
tastiness is a complex, nonnatural property. Later, however, a colleague
shows Tim all the tastiness insights that science
has to offer (e.g., the evolutionary insight that chocolate is tasty
because it is a great source of energy). After considering the
scientific evidence, Tim replies: “Ok, I may lose
some plausibility points here, but my original, nonnatural
hypothesis has gained me so many plausibility points that this loss
poses no threat to my overall theory.”
This would clearly be an unsatisfying reply. Why? Well, for the same
reason as before. Due to the importance of taking into account both
perspectives when investigating how some mental processes (and the
involved entities) fit into reality, the plausibility of Tim’s “metaphysics of taste” should be considered
uncertain until we weigh in the external evidence. The
plausibility of Tim’s view surely depends, among
other things, on how well it fits with the best scientific understanding
of tastiness. And, thus, Tim cannot reasonably
assign a high number of plausibility points to his metaphysics and then
compare this number with the number of points he loses in virtue of the
scientific facts. Instead, the scientific facts help to
determine the plausibility of his metaphysics in the first place.
Therefore, Tim cannot reach his preferred final
score. The same holds for Enoch, and for the same reasons.
One last comment before we recapitulate and move on. Enoch’s
readiness to distribute a high number of plausibility points to his
metaphysical picture before having taken into account the external
perspective is a perfect example of what I take to be methodologically
problematic about many nonnaturalist views. This readiness, I suspect,
results from a mindset that already devalues the external perspective’s
bearing on metaethical
theorizing. For, without such a devaluation, how could we confidently
assign a high number of plausibility points to our nonnaturalist
metaphysical picture before having even looked at the external evidence?
We could only do so, it seems, if we already presupposed that,
whatever the external perspective may have to offer, it would
be relatively unimportant. I suspect that this presupposition underlies
many nonnaturalist approaches. It is a bias that manifests on the
methodological level; it manifests in how (some) nonnaturalists approach
metaethical
theorizing.
Let us recapitulate. Our methodological
considerations, if correct, establish the following: When trying to
explain how ethical deliberation and what it is distinctively about fits
into reality, we should take into account and try to reconcile the
external and the internal data. The argument from ethical phenomenology
violates this methodological guideline by drawing metaphysical
conclusions on solely phenomenological grounds. Therefore, the argument
fails.
What options are nonnaturalists left with? Well, they could give up
the argument from ethical phenomenology. But let us not go there (yet).
Alternatively, they could feel inclined to dig in their heels and
respond: “The external perspective is simply irrelevant for the context
of ethics because the fundamental ethical entities are
nonnatural.” If true, this response might exculpate the
argument from ethical phenomenology. Unfortunately, however, responding
in this way is not a real option because it obviously begs the question
against naturalism. Metaethical arguments should establish the
metaphysical status of ethical entities, not presuppose it.
So, only one option remains for nonnaturalists who want to hold on to
the argument from ethical phenomenology. They need an
independent argument for the irrelevance of the external
perspective. If they were to establish, somehow, that the external
perspective couldn’t contribute anything useful regarding the
nature of ethical deliberation (and the nature of the involved
entities), construing a moral metaphysics on solely phenomenological
grounds might turn out legitimate after all. With such an independent
argument, nonnaturalists could meet the Challenge from Lost Perspective.
The Intuitive Otherness of
Ethics
Our previous discussion has shown that if nonnaturalists want to hold
on to the argument from ethical phenomenology, they have to
independently establish the irrelevance of the external perspective in
metaethical theorizing.
Their task is, in other words, to establish the “otherness” of ethics.
How to do that?
One particularly influential consideration in favor of the otherness
of ethics is the so-called just too different intuition.
Just
Too Different Intuition (JTD). Intuitively, there is an unbridgeable gap
between ethical and natural facts (truths, properties, and
relations).
JTD
is wide-spread across the nonnaturalist literature.
Due to this prevalence, it is worth taking a closer look at two
exemplary “applications.”
Start with Enoch. When he develops his argument from deliberative
indispensability, he claims—in what I take to be the quintessential
paragraph of his book—that the normative truths we are committed to qua
deliberators must be nonnatural.
Because only normative truths can answer the normative questions I
ask myself in deliberation, nothing less than a normative truth suffices
for deliberation. And because the kind of normative facts that are
indispensable for deliberation are just so different from
naturalist, not-obviously-normative facts and truths, the chances of a
naturalist reduction seem rather grim. […] The gap between the normative
and the natural, considered from the point of view of a deliberating
agent, seems unbridgeable. (Enoch 2011, 80, my emphasis)
Enoch’s point is straightforward: From the first-person perspective
of deliberating agents, the normative truths we are looking for seem
so different from natural truths that they couldn’t possibly be
natural. Thus, we get the otherness of ethics.
The second exemplary application of JTD is Derek Parfit’s
normativity objection against normative naturalism. To get his objection started,
Parfit compares the following two statements:
(B) You ought to jump.
(C) Jumping would do most to fulfill
your present, fully informed desires […].
Parfit observes that appeals to normative facts like (B) strike us to be very different from appeals to
natural facts like (C). In his own words: “Given the
difference between the meanings of claims like (B)
and (C), such claims could not, I believe, state the
same fact.”
Again, the argument is straightforward: Since appeals to normative
facts seem so different from appeals to natural facts,
normative facts couldn’t be natural. Thus, we get the otherness of
ethics.
Now, does this work? Could JTD-based arguments be used as independent arguments for
the irrelevance of the external perspective in metaethical theorizing? I don’t think so for the
following two reasons: Firstly, Enoch’s and Parfit’s considerations are
themselves instances of the argument from ethical phenomenology.
According to both authors, phenomenology reveals that ethical
facts are very different from natural ones; JTD is a phenomenological
datum, after all. Thus, using the intuition to establish the
(metaphysical) otherness of ethical entities is just another instance of
the argument from ethical phenomenology. Appeals to JTD are not independent.
They merely move the bump in the rug.
Secondly, relying on JTD in order to establish the otherness of
ethics violates our second methodological guideline (above). Recall: When investigating any mental
process, we should expect that the internal data will look very
different from the external data. I am inclined to speculate that this
is due to the nature of human consciousness (whatever it is). We inhabit
a subjective perspective from which experiences come with a “something
it is like.” They come with a, well, phenomenology. So, it is not
surprising at all that these experiences, as had “from within,” are
described very differently from the “external story” about what is going
on when we’re having them. This suggests the following: For any property
\(P\) that presents itself as part of
your phenomenology, the differences between, on the one hand, your
phenomenological impression of the nature of \(P\) and, on the other hand, the best
external story about the nature of \(P\), provide no reason whatsoever
to think that \(P\) is a nonnatural
property. We find the same “unbridgeable gap” in the case of water and
H\(_{2}\)O (see above). For these two reasons, JTD cannot help
nonnaturalists to meet the Challenge from Lost Perspective.
We are back at square one. We haven’t met the Challenge from Lost Perspective yet; we
haven’t established the otherness of ethics. And without the otherness
of ethics, the argument from ethical phenomenology does not even get off
the ground. Now, there are probably more ways to try to meet the Challenge from Lost Perspective.
Nonnaturalists will have more to offer than appeals to JTD. But we won’t turn to
these alternative attempts here. Instead, let me point out an
interesting big-picture conclusion that follows from our discussion.
It has become clear that there are two general strategies for
nonnaturalists. Either they (1) solely rely
on the phenomenological perspective, or (2)
they take into account and try to reconcile both perspectives. The first strategy falls prey to the Challenge from Lost Perspective.
Disregarding the external perspective in one’s (metaphysical)
interpretations of ethical deliberation is methodologically
unreasonable. Moreover, any purely phenomenology-based attempt
to warrant the exclusion of external evidence just moves the bump in the
rug. So, here is the big-picture conclusion: If nonnaturalists want to
go with the first strategy, they first have to justify the
legitimacy of this strategy—but this can only be done by taking the second strategy. Thus, nonnaturalists must move
beyond a purely phenomenology-based strategy in any case. They must, on
pain of methodological unreasonableness, embrace the external
perspective.
However, embracing the external perspective constitutes something
close to a paradigm shift for nonnaturalists. As far as I am aware, the
most prominent positive arguments for nonnaturalism are versions of the
argument from ethical phenomenology. They all maintain, in one way or
another, that some part of ethical phenomenology is best explained by
the existence of nonnatural ethical entities. This raises what I take to
be the million-dollar question for nonnaturalists: Is there a way to
legitimize the argument from ethical phenomenology that takes into
account both perspectives?
Let me say this much here: I believe there is good reason why
nonnaturalists traditionally fend off the relevance of the external
perspective in metaethics. If this dam broke, an entire ocean of
external, empirical evidence concerning, say, the evolutionary function
of deliberation or the origins of ethical intuitions would suddenly have
to be weighed in. All of this poses an obvious threat to the
nonnaturalist project: It may seem rather unlikely that the existence of
nonnatural entities will turn out to remain a better
explanation of ethical phenomenology than some externally
and internally informed account devoid of such entities. This partly explains, I think, the
typical nonnaturalist reluctance to acknowledge the external perspective
as relevant for metaethical theorizing. But if our
considerations are correct, nonnaturalists do not have much choice; they
must overcome this reluctance.
Conclusion
Nonnaturalists believe that ethical thought and talk involve (robust
or not-so-robust) nonnatural ethical entities. In this paper, we have
focused on the most prevalent positive argument for this view, the
argument from ethical phenomenology. According to it, the claim that
some ethical entities are nonnatural is part of the best explanation of
why ethical phenomenology is the way it is. Our main conclusion is that
the argument is methodologically unreasonable.
We started by stating the goals of metaethical investigations. These investigations
try to explain how ethical deliberation—and what, if anything, it is
distinctively about—fits into reality. We then argued, quite generally,
that investigations of mental processes should take into account and try
to reconcile both the internal (phenomenological) and the external
(broadly: scientific) perspectives. This, we claimed, is where the
argument from ethical phenomenology fails: It draws metaphysical
conclusions that are solely based on internal, phenomenological
observations. The argument, in other words, blinds out the external
perspective. Hence our main challenge:
Challenge from Lost
Perspective.
Proponents of the argument from ethical phenomenology must tell
us why the external perspective on ethical thought and talk does not
need to be taken into account before they conclude, on solely
phenomenological grounds, that ethical thought and talk are about
nonnatural entities.
In order to meet this challenge, we said, nonnaturalists must provide
an independent argument for the irrelevance of the external perspective.
We discussed one strategy to this effect that involves the just too
different intuition. We rejected this strategy for two reasons. The
(maybe) more important one was that the just too different intuition
cannot provide us with an independent argument for the
irrelevance of the external perspective because any argument based on it
would just be another instance of the argument from ethical
phenomenology.
Our big-picture conclusion was that nonnaturalists must move away
from a purely phenomenology-based strategy. Such strategies are
methodologically unreasonable because they do not take into account the
external perspective; they are unreasonable, that is, unless we
already knew that the external perspective is irrelevant for metaethical theorizing.
However, to establish that, nonnaturalists would have to, well,
move beyond a purely phenomenology-based strategy. Otherwise, they would
be arguing in circles, begging the question against those who believe
that the external perspective is relevant for metaethical theorizing.
The big-picture conclusion is especially interesting once we
acknowledge that most of nonnaturalism’s supportive considerations are
entirely phenomenology-based. What exactly this
means for the prospects of nonnaturalism is a topic for another
occasion. I do think, however, that the loss of the argument from
ethical phenomenology leads to a significant decrease in plausibility
points—at least as long as nonnaturalists do not defend their approach
in a way that isn’t question-begging on the methodological level.
One final question: Could nonnaturalists reject the Challenge from Lost Perspective as
illegitimate? I don’t think so. The challenge represents a hard-to-doubt
methodological idea: When starting to investigate how any
mental process—and what this mental process is distinctively about—fits
into reality, we should be open to all kinds of evidence, external and
internal. We should not prematurely, that is, without further
argument, blind out or devaluate a whole
perspective on the mental process we are interested in—especially so if
this perspective has proven highly resourceful in the context of other
mental processes. Ultimately, the best account of the nature of ethical
deliberation will be one that hasn’t lost perspective.