In this paper, I develop a methodological challenge for ethical
nonnaturalism. The challenge is methodological because it concerns the
way many nonnaturalists argue for their views. I suggest that there is
an overlooked problem for a central and prevalent positive argument for
nonnaturalism, the argument from ethical phenomenology. This
problem, I intend to show, ultimately renders nonnaturalism
indefensible—at least in so far as the view is solely based on this
argument.
Let us start by clarifying the goals of metaethical theorizing. Here
is a useful characterization:
[Metaethics is the] theoretical activity which aims to explain how
actual ethical thought and talk—and what (if anything) that thought and
talk is distinctively about—fits into reality. (McPherson and Plunkett 2018, 3)
That is, metaethics concerns the nature of moral thought, moral
language, moral facts, moral properties, and moral knowledge.
Nonnaturalists believe that ethical thought and talk involves
nonnatural entities. What does that mean? Nonnatural
entities are thought to be categorically distinct from, or “something
over and above,” the natural (Enoch 2011, 101).
Nonnaturalists typically do not claim that all ethical entities
are nonnatural. Some ethical entities are “mixed”; they consist in a
combination of natural and nonnatural entities. (For example, the fact
that Anna’s hitting Ben is wrong consists in a natural part—the
hitting—and a nonnatural part—the hitting’s wrongness.) But, crucially,
nonnaturalists claim that the most fundamental ethical entities
are “purely” nonnatural (cf. Scanlon 2014, 36–37). In this sense,
they are categorically distinct from, or something over and above,
natural entities.
Why believe that ethical entities are nonnatural? One prevalent
nonnaturalist argument—the argument from ethical phenomenology—takes the
form of an inference to the best explanation and consists of two steps:
First, describe the phenomenology of ethical deliberation. Second, show
that the best explanation for it—the best explanation for why
this is what ethical deliberation is like—involves the
existence of nonnatural entities.
The typical naturalist response to the argument from ethical
phenomenology is that there are better explanations for the
phenomenology of ethical deliberation than the existence of nonnatural
entities. However, we will pursue a different path here. Our
methodological challenge is logically prior to responses of this kind.
We will try to show, not that there are better explanations, but that,
quite generally, the outlined way of arguing for the existence of
nonnatural entities is methodologically problematic. In short, our
charge will be that it is methodologically unreasonable to explain or
interpret ethical phenomenology by making metaphysical claims without
taking into account another, more “external” perspective on ethical
thought and talk.
Here is our plan. Section 1 introduces two
distinct perspectives on mental processes and argues that both
perspectives are important when it comes to understanding how these
processes fit into reality. Ethical deliberation is a mental process,
and so it will be worth reflecting on how, in general, philosophers
should approach these processes. Based on the insights gathered here,
section 2 introduces the Challenge from Lost Perspective in the context
of David Enoch’s work (Enoch 2011).
This section is the heart of the paper. Section 3 discusses two nonnaturalist attempts to meet
the challenge (from Enoch 2011; and Parfit 2011). Both attempts involve the
so-called “just too different intuition.” I show why they cannot
succeed. At this point, it will hopefully have become clear that the
argument from ethical phenomenology runs into a serious methodological
problem. It can only get off the ground by presupposing something
opponents of nonnaturalism (whether reductionists, expressivists, or
error-theorists) deny, namely, that the external perspective is
irrelevant for metaethical theorizing. The argument, in other words,
begs the question on a methodological level. The final section sums up
our main points and recommends a strategy to future nonnaturalists.
Reconciling Two Perspectives
As Mark Timmons (1999) and
Terence Cuneo (2007b) have
helpfully emphasized, the metaethical project can be described as a
twofold endeavor. The first part of it is the “internal accommodation
project”: developing a theory of ethical thought and talk that fits well
with “deeply embedded assumptions” of our ordinary ethical thought and
practice (Cuneo 2007b,
854). In other words, the internal accommodation project aims
for the theory that best accounts for our internal perspective on
ethics, our ethical phenomenology. For example, it is (presumably) a
deeply embedded assumption of ethical thought and talk that if an agent
has a moral belief, she is pro tanto motivated to act accordingly. So, a
plausible metaethical view should account for this feature.
The second part of the metaethical project is the “external
accommodation project.” Its goal is to come up with a metaethical theory
that fits well with the “scientific world view.” For example, a
metaethical view should, at least, not directly contradict scientific
insights into human nature as presented by, say, evolutionary biology or
empirical psychology. Ideally, a metaethical view would get further
evidential support from scientific research such that we, ultimately,
get a unified “phenomenological-cum-scientific” theory of ethical
thought and talk. However, it might also turn out that the ethical
domain is “autonomous,” and that scientific insights are simply
irrelevant when it comes to the fundamental ethical entities. If so, the
external accommodation project would (maybe trivially) be completed, but
more about that later.
These two explanatory projects form the basis of our challenge to
nonnaturalism. In the following, we will
distinguish the internal perspective from the external
perspective. The internal perspective delivers the stuff relevant for
the project of internal accommodation; it grants access to some process
or practice “from within.” The external perspective delivers what is
necessary for the project of external accommodation; it provides
insights into some process or practice “from without,” by means of
investigations that are not phenomenological.
Importantly, I take the external accommodation project to cover more
than just the methods of the natural sciences. What I mean is the a
posteriori investigation of a process or practice that goes beyond
phenomenological observations. For example, an anthropological
investigation of the practice of monetary transactions counts as
external. Such an investigation looks at the practice “from
without,” for instance, by focusing on the societal advantages of trade.
It is based on insights gathered from the external perspective
(and not based on the “phenomenology of money experiences”).
Back to nonnaturalism. Is the idea that there are nonnatural entities
the result of external or internal accommodation? As we are about to see
in the following section, the claim typically results from an
internal accommodation. Nonnaturalists usually start with
ethical phenomenology and then proceed to explain it via metaphysical
hypotheses that involve nonnatural entities.
But, importantly, these hypotheses are not directly “revealed” by
internal, phenomenological analyses. Instead, they are
interpretations of our phenomenology. And these interpretations
are part of the nonnaturalists’ internal accommodation project because
they are solely based on phenomenological appearances.
Now, let us illustrate how both perspectives on mental processes can
be brought together. Take the example of human disgust. We could either
start investigating disgust “from within,” that is, with its
what-it-is-like. This would involve, say, analyzing the stream
of thoughts and feelings present in disgust episodes. Or we could assume
the external perspective and explain, “from without,” what anchors
disgust reactions in the empirical world. This would involve, for
instance, analyzing (neuro)physiological processes and disgust’s
evolutionary function.
Start with the internal perspective. What is it like to encounter
rotten food? You feel a strong inclination or desire not to get too
close to the food. Touching it with your bare skin strikes you as
repulsive. You might experience nausea. You want to get rid of the
rotten food as quickly as possible. And if you imagine having
accidentally put it into your mouth, your reactions further escalate.
Yuck, away with it!
Now, trying to come up with a theory of disgust, you might discover
that there are many other disgusting things. There are greasy, sticky,
or malodorous objects, blood, mutilation, waste, hygiene violations, and
even some animals (e.g., rats, cockroaches, worms, or flies). This can
seem quite puzzling: Why is it that we react to all these
different things in the same way? Do
they have something in common that might explain our reaction to them?
Is there more to find out and understand about disgust than we can
observe from the internal perspective?
Of course there is. But in order to find out more, we need to assume
the external perspective. According to a widely accepted scientific
theory, disgust is a behavioral extension of the immune system (Rozin, Haidt and
McCauley 2008). It helps us to avoid pathogens. Very roughly:
disgust is triggered when we encounter something potentially infectious,
which helps us to avoid it. So, assuming the external perspective on
disgust is quite illuminating. Undoubtedly, our understanding has been
enriched by it. On top of the detailed phenomenological descriptions of
what it is like to experience disgust, we now also understand what
anchors disgust in the world as conceived by the natural sciences. We
have a better grasp of its “point”—of why beings like us are disgusted
in the first place. We also better understand why there is a whole range
of different things that evoke the same disgust reactions. Blood, greasy
objects, and rats are all “signs” for the presence of pathogens—and thus
to be avoided. In a first and preliminary attempt, we might (partly)
characterize disgustingness as something along the lines of being an
indicator of the above-some-threshold likelihood of the presence of
pathogens.
I take it that disgustingness is a good example because of its
evaluative or normative dimension. What renders a
property evaluative? McDowell (1985,
119–121) distinguishes non-evaluative properties that
“merely” causally influence our responses from evaluative properties
that merit certain responses. His criterion for assigning a
property to the evaluative camp is “the possibility of criticism” (1985,
119). Now, I think it is fair to say that a dead rat in one’s
fridge merits disgust. If Fred discovered a dead rat in his
fridge and showed no signs of disgust while happily starting to eat the
open bowl of yoghurt that has been standing right next to the cadaver,
we would ask ourselves what is wrong with him. Thus, I side with
McDowell and state that disgustingness has an evaluative dimension. So,
even in the case of properties with an evaluative or normative
dimension, external insights can be quite resourceful.
The above considerations set the stage for the main claim of the
current section:
Methodologically speaking, an investigation of the nature of
any mental process (and the involved entities) should take into
account, and try to reconcile, both the internal and the
external perspective.
Let me elaborate. Suppose Danielle wants to investigate the nature of
disgust. She only cares for a phenomenological investigation, and so she
never even considers taking into account what the sciences have to say.
Scrutinizing disgust phenomenology for a few days, she ultimately
concludes that disgustingness is a nonnatural property that human beings
can apprehend via a special, intuition-like faculty. Some otherwise
seemingly unrelated objects (blood and cockroaches, say) instantiate
this property, and somehow the human mind can recognize it. Note that
nothing in the phenomenology of disgust speaks against Danielle’s
disgust nonnaturalism; her view accounts (we may assume) for all the
relevant phenomenological data quite well. But now suppose that
Danielle’s friend Fatima decides to tell her all the scientific insights
about human disgust reactions. She tells her that disgust tracks
possible sources of infection and that scientists consider this tracking
function as its evolutionary point. Now, here is a crucial question:
Coming to learn all the external facts about human disgust reactions,
should Danielle’s confidence in disgust nonnaturalism
change?
I believe that, upon learning the external facts, it would be
rational for Danielle to change her confidence in disgust nonnaturalism.
These newly learned facts suggest—and this is a crucial step in my
argument—that disgustingness is closely metaphysically linked
to something quite natural: the likely presence of pathogens. It is due
to this suggested metaphysical link that Danielle should take her
disgust nonnaturalism to be less plausible than before. Coming to know the external
evidence, it is rational for Danielle to decrease her
confidence in the idea that disgustingness is something categorically
distinct, something “over and above,” the natural. It must now seem
more likely to her that disgustingness fits into reality by
being a natural property. (Note that Danielle now understands
why blood and cockroaches instantiate disgustingness.) Consequently, she
should decrease her confidence in the idea that disgustingness is a
nonnatural property.
Based on these considerations, we may formulate a (not entirely
catchy) slogan: External evidence can shift the plausibility of
metaphysical explanations of the phenomenology of mental processes.
As we just saw, the external perspective on human disgust reactions
influences the plausibility of Danielle’s disgust nonnaturalism. In
virtue of plausibility shifts of this kind, it is methodologically
unreasonable to draw metaphysical conclusions about the nature of
disgustingness on solely phenomenological grounds. If we want
to find out how any mental process fits into the reality that the
empirical sciences have taught us so much about, it would be a bad idea
to disregard possibly relevant empirical evidence.
We may put two points on record. Firstly, the internal and the
external perspectives on disgust complement each other.
Reconciling them helps us “anchor” disgust in the natural world.
Moreover, adding the external perspective to Danielle’s investigation
changes the plausibility of her solely phenomenology-based metaphysical
account of disgustingness. So, if you want to write a book titled
“Disgust: What It Is and How It Fits Into Reality” you should take the
external perspective into account. Not doing so would be
methodologically unreasonable.
Secondly, our two perspectives deliver characterizations of disgust
that look very different but are intimately linked. For example, part of
a phenomenological description of disgust is the “yuck”-reaction, a
strong inclination to get rid of the disgusting object. There seems to
be a large gap between this description and the external story, which
includes, besides a list of facts about neurophysiology and muscle
twitches, that disgust is an evolutionary tool for tracking and avoiding
possibly infectious objects. Despite this gap, there is an intimate
connection. Plausibly, the disgustingness of the dead rat in your fridge
(partly) consists in the likelihood of its being a source of infection.
A close metaphysical link between the dead rat’s disgustingness
and some set of scientifically accessible properties can, at least,
not be ruled out.,
These two methodological conclusions, I think, apply to mental
processes more generally. The case of disgust suggests that, whenever we
investigate a mental process, we should take into account both
perspectives on it—unless there is reason to believe that one
perspective is utterly irrelevant for investigating the respective
mental process. As long as we don’t know about such
a reason, we should be open to all the internal and external evidence we
might get hold on—which lets us formulate two methodological
guidelines:
1. When you interpret or explain the
phenomenology of mental processes (and the involved entities), take into
account both the internal and the external perspective on the respective
processes.
2. While the internal and the
external perspective might describe mental processes (and the involved
entities) in very different ways, do not take this to rule out that the
entities mentioned in both descriptions are closely metaphysically
linked.
In this section, we have argued that an investigation of the nature
of any mental process should take into account, and try to reconcile,
both the internal and the external perspective. This will serve as a
fruitful ground for our objection to the argument from ethical
phenomenology. As we are going to claim in the upcoming section, the
argument violates our first methodological guideline; it constructs a
moral metaphysics on phenomenological grounds without taking
into account the external perspective.
The Challenge from Lost
Perspective
Ethical nonnaturalists have a rich history of constructing ethical
ontologies out of phenomenological analyses of ethical deliberation.
They answer the question of how ethical entities fit into reality by
stating that reality comprises more than the sciences would have us
believe. There are, they claim, nonnatural ethical entities. Depending
on what particular view we are dealing with, these entities are truths,
facts, properties, or relations. But whatever they are, the crucial idea
is that they are something categorically distinct from, something over
and above, the natural. Now, let us take a closer look at
one version of the argument from ethical phenomenology.
David Enoch advocates the argument from the moral implications of
objectivity (Enoch 2011,
16–49). It runs as follows: In cases of preference
conflicts—say, about where to have dinner tonight—it intuitively seems
that we should solve the conflict impartially. It would not be okay to
declare that Mark’s preference for Italian is more important than Anna’s
preference for Indian. Intuitively, they should agree that their
preferences count the same, and then find a solution from here on out.
Clearly, none of their preferences is mistaken. On the other
hand, in a moral conflict, it intuitively seems that the appropriate
response is not impartial. For example, if I disagree with
someone claiming that not a single refugee from Ukraine should be
allowed to cross the German border, she strikes me as mistaken.
It seems to me that my opinion has some objective backing—and that an
impartial treatment of our “moral preferences” would be deeply
misguided. So, there is an internal, phenomenological difference between
moral disagreements and conflicts of preference. The former ones have
(or seem to have) an objectively right answer. The latter ones don’t.
And this, according to Enoch, is “best explained” by a robust
nonnaturalist realism (Enoch 2018, 40; 2011, 16–49).
This argument fits the general pattern of the argument from ethical
phenomenology. Starting with phenomenological observations about the
differences between moral disagreements and conflicts of preference, it
draws a metaphysical conclusion to explain this difference. So, the
argument is a suitable target for our methodological worries.
There are, of course, many other versions of the argument from
ethical phenomenology. However, in the following, I will
mostly rely on considerations from Enoch (2011) because they strike me as
particularly straightforward. I hope it will become clear that my
methodological worries can be extrapolated to different versions of the
argument from ethical phenomenology proposed by other nonnaturalist
authors. Let us turn to these worries now.
Metaethics, we said, is the project of explaining how ethical thought
and talk, and what it is about, fits into reality. Now, trivially,
reality does not exhaust itself in phenomenology. As the case of disgust
served to show, the phenomenology of a mental process might only be one
side of the coin. Sometimes, there is another side; a side that is only
revealed if we look at the process from the external perspective.
Therefore—and in the absence of reasons to the contrary—we should take
into account both perspectives when trying to understand how a
mental process and the involved truths, facts, properties, or relations
fit into reality. If you want to write a book titled “Ethical Thought
and Talk: What It Is and How It Fits Into Reality” and you are not
planning to even look at the subject matter from an external
perspective, chances are you are missing something relevant. This would
be methodologically unreasonable. We already saw how external evidence
can shift the plausibility of metaphysical claims that solely rest on
phenomenological observations. Due to the possibility of such shifts,
you should at least give the external evidence a shot at informing your
metaphysics. And so we may raise the following challenge:
Challenge from Lost
Perspective.
Proponents of the argument from ethical phenomenology must tell
us why the external perspective on ethical thought and talk does not
need to be taken into account before they conclude, on solely
phenomenological grounds, that ethical thought and talk is about
nonnatural entities.
There is a slight chance that nonnaturalists remain unimpressed by
this challenge. They might ask: What could the external perspective
possibly contribute to our understanding of ethics? I have a
quick and a not-so-quick reply. Here’s the quick one: The question of
how ethical thought and talk fit into reality is a descriptive question
about the reality we live in. We already know that there are many truths
about this reality that cannot be discovered by phenomenological
investigations. Therefore, it strikes me as quite commonsensical to at
least entertain the possibility that the external
perspective—which has proven quite resourceful in teaching us about the
nature of reality—has something to contribute here. But since
this answer might be considered too superficial, let me try again and
present my not-so-quick reply.
Suppose we have two different explanations of the phenomenology of
ethical deliberation on the table. One of them is nonnaturalism,
according to which the “currencies” of ethical deliberation—values and
reasons—essentially involve nonnatural entities. The other one is a
broadly “Humean” explanation, according to which values and reasons are
grounded in our conative, desire-like attitudes. They are, as Finlay (2014,
249–250) nicely puts it, “shadow[s] cast by our desires […].”
How could the external perspective contribute anything to this debate
between the nonnaturalist and the Humean?
Here is one possibility: It might turn out that, from an external
perspective, ethical deliberation is an evolutionarily acquired tool for
“conative mind-management,” that is, for dealing with conflicts between
and hierarchizing our conative attitudes.
As human beings with a capacity for imagination, a limitless time
horizon, deeply entrenched social needs, and thus a multitude of
conflicting attitudes, we face an enormous evolutionary challenge:
managing our minds in order to be coherent agents, and then coordinating
our actions with our fellow community members. Investigating the human
mind from the external perspective of evolutionary anthropology, we
might encounter the hypothesis that ethical deliberation is an
evolutionary, cultural tool for solving this challenge (cf. Tomasello 2016;
Henrich
2016). Let me be clear: I do not want to
argue for this hypothesis. My main point is conditional, but it suffices
to answer the question of what the external perspective could possibly
contribute. If the external perspective revealed something along these
lines, this would (much like in the case of disgust) shift the
plausibility of the nonnaturalist and the Humean explanations. How?
Well, the nonnaturalist explanation would lose some plausibility points,
whereas the Humean explanation would gain some. Why? Because metaethics
is concerned with explaining how ethical thought and talk fit into
reality and because, as argued above, we should take into account, and
try to reconcile, both perspectives in this process. If the “external
point” of ethical deliberation turned out to be conative
mind-management, this would fit better with a broadly Humean view,
according to which there is a close metaphysical link between
values and reasons on the one hand, and conative attitudes on the other
hand. Since nonnaturalists reject such a link, their explanation would
lose some plausibility points. Additionally, combining a Humean view
with our stipulated external story would promise a more parsimonious
account of how ethical thought and talk fit into reality.
This is how the external perspective could contribute to the
metaethical debate between the nonnaturalist and the Humean.
The outlined external story about the evolutionary point of ethical
deliberation is, of course, hypothetical. But our general methodological
consideration is not. We argued that external investigations into mental
processes can (and often do) shift the plausibility of (metaphysical)
interpretations of the respective phenomenologies. Thus, we should take
into account the external perspective when developing and assessing
these interpretations. Importantly, this holds even if external evidence
ultimately turns out to be irrelevant for metaethical
theorizing. Even in that case, it would still be true that disregarding
the external perspective would have been methodologically unreasonable;
when we started the investigation, we simply didn’t know.
This means that proponents of the argument from ethical phenomenology
face a problem. They proceed in a methodologically unreasonable way.
They construct a controversial moral metaphysics on phenomenological
grounds without taking into account the external evidence.
Let us put a concrete example on the table. Enoch’s second main
argument for nonnaturalism is the argument from deliberative
indispensability. Like his first argument, it is a version of the
argument from ethical phenomenology. When introducing it, Enoch
explicitly disregards the external perspective as irrelevant.
Had we been here in the explanatory business—trying to explain
action, or perhaps even deliberation, from a third-person point of
view—perhaps desires would have been enough (though I doubt it). But the
whole point of the argument of this chapter is the focus on the
first-person, deliberative perspective. And from this perspective,
desires are not often relevant, and whether they are or are not, the
normative commitment is—though perhaps implicit—inescapable. […] [W]e
need normative truths even if, viewed from an external perspective, our
desires suffice in order to cause our actions and then explain them,
because, when deliberating, we know our desires are merely our
desires. (Enoch 2011, 76,
footnotes left out)
Interestingly, Enoch seems to agree that there is an external
perspective from which deliberation could be investigated. But then he
dismisses the relevance of possible external insights—desires
could help to explain the nature of deliberation—for the
purposes of his chapter because desires play no important
internal role on the conscious mental stage of deliberation. The whole point of his chapter, he
suggests, is to better understand the nature of normative truths from a
first-person point of view. And, by the end of the chapter, he
concludes that we should best think of these truths as nonnatural. So,
according to what we have said, Enoch’s approach is methodologically
unreasonable; his two main arguments for ethical nonnaturalism construct
a moral metaphysics on phenomenological grounds without taking into
account the external perspective.
To be fair, however, we should mention that Enoch does consider the
external perspective on ethical deliberation later in his book (Enoch 2011, 151–175).
There, he discusses Sharon Street’s Darwinian Dilemma for moral
realism (2006) as an
epistemological challenge to his view. We won’t dive into the details.
For our purposes, it suffices to focus on the way Enoch replies
to Street’s dilemma. First, he reminds us that metaethics is about
scoring plausibility points. Ultimately, he says, metaethicists offer
package deals, and the one with the most plausibility points wins. In
this spirit, Enoch preliminarily remarks that his view does not need to
do “better than competing metanormative theories in every respect,
with regard to every problem” (Enoch 2011, 167). And so he sets out to
show that his two positive arguments for nonnaturalism scored him more
points than he is about to lose due to the epistemological challenge.
Ultimately, after having presented his solution to the challenge, he
states: “Let me not give the impression that this suggested way of
coping with the epistemological challenge is ideal. […] [P]erhaps Robust
Realism does lose some plausibility points here. But not, it seems to
me, too many, and certainly not as many as you may have thought” (2011, 175). So, Enoch believes that his
two main arguments for the existence of nonnatural ethical facts—two
different versions of the argument from ethical phenomenology—generate
such a significant number of plausibility points that later objections
to his view, formulated from an external perspective, can be met via an
inferior solution—because he doesn’t lose as many points as he
previously scored.
I find this rather unconvincing. It will take the rest of this
section to explain why. We argued earlier that, when
interpreting or explaining mental processes, it is methodologically
unreasonable to draw metaphysical conclusions on solely phenomenological
grounds. Now, start by noting that this is precisely what Enoch does
when he develops his positive arguments for nonnaturalism—even
if it is true that he later confronts his metaphysical
conclusions with an objection formulated from the external perspective.
For all we said above, the external evidence regarding the nature of
ethical deliberation may have significantly decreased the
plausibility of Enoch’s metaphysical conclusions—in which case we should
never have drawn them in the first place.
But nonnaturalists might want to object: Does it really matter
when we take into account the external perspective? Enoch
clearly does take it into account, so where is the problem? As long as
we do take it into account at some point, we should be fine,
shouldn’t we? I don’t think so. It actually does matter when we
take into account the external perspective because as long as we
haven’t, we cannot assign plausibility points to our
metaphysics. Without taking into account the external evidence, we
simply cannot know how plausible our solely phenomenology-based
metaphysical explanation is. But this is a complicated thought, so let
me elaborate a little.
As we just saw, Enoch is quite confident that, despite his less than
ideal solution to the epistemological challenge, he “certainly” does not
lose as many points as he previously scored. Let us reconsider his
approach in light of our methodological worries. Enoch first explicitly
disregards a perspective it is, we argued, methodologically unreasonable
to disregard. This allows him to draw his metaphysical conclusions
precisely in the way the way we claimed to be methodologically
unreasonable. Later, Enoch confronts his metaphysical picture with
objections from the perspective that he previously disregarded. Doing
so, he finds that his metaphysical picture, which was drawn, again, in a
methodologically unreasonable way, gained such a high (!) number of
plausibility points that they “certainly” cannot be outweighed by
objections generated by the perspective whose taking into account would
have stopped his conclusions from being methodologically unreasonable in
the first place.
This strikes me as fishy. When we construct a metaphysics on solely
phenomenological grounds, we should expect that, once we add the
external perspective to our investigation, the plausibility of our
metaphysics might change. (Recall Danielle’s disgust
nonnaturalism.) But this means that we cannot—and, importantly,
Enoch cannot—confidently distribute plausibility points to his
metaphysics before weighing in the external evidence. This, I
think, is a crucial implication of our earlier methodological
considerations. If these considerations are correct, if drawing
metaphysical conclusions on solely phenomenological grounds is
methodologically unreasonable, then the plausibility of these
conclusions should be considered uncertain as long as we
haven’t weighed in the external evidence. In other words, our
methodological considerations suggest that the number of plausibility
points Enoch’s moral metaphysics scores itself depends on how
well it fits with the external evidence. Therefore, Enoch’s allocation
of any particular number of plausibility points to his
metaphysics—let alone a high number of points—is unwarranted.
Enoch simply cannot know how plausible his metaphysics is until he has
taken the external evidence into account.
Consider an analogous case. Tim wants to investigate the nature of
taste. At the beginning of his investigation, he explicitly disregards
the external perspective. His solely phenomenological investigation
leads him to the conclusion that tastiness is a complex, nonnatural
property. Later, however, a colleague shows Tim all the tastiness
insights that science has to offer (e.g., the evolutionary insight that
chocolate is tasty because it is a great source of energy). After
considering the scientific evidence, Tim replies: “Ok, I may lose
some plausibility points here, but my original, nonnatural
hypothesis has gained me so many plausibility points that this loss
poses no threat to my overall theory.”
This would clearly be an unsatisfying reply. Why? Well, for the same
reason as before. Due to the importance of taking into account both
perspectives when investigating how some mental processes (and the
involved entities) fit into reality, the plausibility of Tim’s
“metaphysics of taste” should be considered uncertain until we
weigh in the external evidence. The plausibility of Tim’s view surely
depends, among other things, on how well it fits with the best
scientific understanding of tastiness. And, thus, Tim cannot reasonably
assign a high number of plausibility points to his metaphysics and then
compare this number with the number of points he loses in virtue of the
scientific facts. Instead, the scientific facts help to
determine the plausibility of his metaphysics in the first place.
Therefore, Tim cannot reach his preferred final score. The same holds
for Enoch, and for the same reasons.
One last comment before we recapitulate and move on. Enoch’s
readiness to distribute a high number of plausibility points to his
metaphysical picture before having taken into account the external
perspective is a perfect example of what I take to be methodologically
problematic about many nonnaturalist views. This readiness, I suspect,
results from a mindset that already devaluates the external
perspective’s bearing on metaethical theorizing. For, without such a
devaluation, how could we confidently assign a high number of
plausibility points to our nonnaturalist metaphysical picture before
having even looked at the external evidence? We could only do so, it
seems, if we already presupposed that, whatever the external
perspective may have to offer, it will be relatively unimportant. I
suspect that this presupposition underlies many nonnaturalist
approaches. It is a bias that manifests on the methodological level; it
manifests in how (some) nonnaturalists approach metaethical
theorizing.
Let us recapitulate. Our methodological considerations, if correct,
establish the following: When trying to explain how ethical
deliberation, and what it is distinctively about, fits into reality, we
should take into account and try to reconcile the external and the
internal data. The argument from ethical phenomenology violates this
methodological guideline by drawing metaphysical conclusions on solely
phenomenological grounds. Therefore, the argument fails.
What options are nonnaturalists left with? Well, they could give up
the argument from ethical phenomenology. But let us not go there (yet).
Alternatively, they could feel inclined to dig in their heels and
respond: “The external perspective is simply irrelevant for the context
of ethics because the fundamental ethical entities are
nonnatural.” If true, this response might exculpate the
argument from ethical phenomenology. Unfortunately, however, responding
in this way is not a real option because it obviously begs the question
against naturalism. Metaethical arguments should establish the
metaphysical status of ethical entities, not presuppose it.
So, only one option remains for nonnaturalists who want to hold on to
the argument from ethical phenomenology. They need an
independent argument for the irrelevance of the external
perspective. If they were to establish, somehow, that the external
perspective couldn’t contribute anything useful regarding the
nature of ethical deliberation (and the nature of the involved
entities), construing a moral metaphysics on solely phenomenological
grounds might turn out legitimate after all. With such an independent
argument, nonnaturalists could meet the Challenge from Lost Perspective.
The Intuitive Otherness of
Ethics
Our previous discussion has shown that if nonnaturalists want to hold
on to the argument from ethical phenomenology, they have to
independently establish the irrelevance of the external perspective in
metaethical theorizing. Their task is, in other words, to establish the
“otherness” of ethics. How to do that?
One particularly influential consideration in favor of the otherness
of ethics is the so-called just too different intuition.
Just
Too Different Intuition (JTD). Intuitively, there is an unbridgeable gap
between ethical and natural facts (truths, properties, relations).
JTD
is wide-spread across the nonnaturalist literature.
Due to this prevalence, it is worth taking a closer look at two
exemplary “applications.”
Start with Enoch. When he develops his argument from deliberative
indispensability, he claims—in what I take to be the quintessential
paragraph of his book—that the normative truths we are committed to qua
deliberators must be nonnatural.
Because only normative truths can answer the normative questions I
ask myself in deliberation, nothing less than a normative truth suffices
for deliberation. And because the kind of normative facts that are
indispensable for deliberation are just so different from
naturalist, not-obviously-normative facts and truths, the chances of a
naturalist reduction seem rather grim. […] The gap between the normative
and the natural, considered from the point of view of a deliberating
agent, seems unbridgeable. (Enoch 2011, 80, my emphasis)
Enoch’s point is straightforward: From the first-person perspective
of deliberating agents, the normative truths we are looking for seem
so different from natural truths that they couldn’t possibly be
natural. Thus, we get the otherness of ethics.
The second exemplary application of JTD is Derek Parfit’s
normativity objection against normative naturalism (2011,
324–327). To get his objection started,
Parfit compares the following two statements:
(B) You ought to jump.
(C) Jumping would do most to fulfill
your present, fully informed desires […].
Parfit observes that appeals to normative facts like (B) strike us to be very different from appeals to
natural facts like (C). In his own words: “Given the
difference between the meanings of claims like (B)
and (C), such claims could not, I believe, state the
same fact” (2011,
326).
Again, the argument is straightforward: Since appeals to normative
facts seem so different from appeals to natural facts,
normative facts couldn’t be natural. Thus, we get the otherness of
ethics.
Now, does this work? Could JTD-based arguments be used as independent
arguments for the irrelevance of the external perspective in metaethical
theorizing? I don’t think so for the following two reasons: Firstly,
Enoch’s and Parfit’s considerations are themselves instances of the
argument from ethical phenomenology. According to both authors,
phenomenology reveals that ethical facts are very different
from natural ones; JTD is a phenomenological datum, after all.
Thus, using the intuition to establish the (metaphysical) otherness of
ethical entities is just another instance of the argument from ethical
phenomenology. Appeals to JTD are not independent. They merely move
the bump in the rug.
Secondly, relying on JTD in order to establish the otherness of
ethics violates our second methodological guideline (see 2. above). Recall: When investigating any mental
process, we should expect that the internal data will look very
different from the external data. I am inclined to speculate that this
is due to the nature of human consciousness (whatever it is). We inhabit
a subjective perspective from which experiences come with a “something
it is like.” They come with a, well, phenomenology. So, it is not
surprising at all that these experiences, as had “from within,” are
described very differently from the “external story” about what is going
on when we’re having them. This suggests the following: For any property
\(P\) that presents itself as part of
your phenomenology, the differences between, on the one hand, your
phenomenological impression of the nature of \(P\) and, on the other hand, the best
external story about the nature of \(P\), provide no reason whatsoever
to think that \(P\) is a nonnatural
property. We find the same “unbridgeable gap” in the case of water and
H\(_{2}\)O (see footnote 14 above). For these two reasons, JTD cannot help
nonnaturalists to meet the Challenge from Lost Perspective.
We are back at square one. We haven’t met the Challenge from Lost Perspective yet; we
haven’t established the otherness of ethics. And without the otherness
of ethics, the argument from ethical phenomenology does not even get off
the ground. Now, there are probably more ways to try to meet the Challenge from Lost Perspective.
Nonnaturalists will have more to offer than appeals to JTD. But we won’t turn to
these alternative attempts here. Instead, let me point out an
interesting big-picture conclusion that follows from our discussion.
It has become clear that there are two general strategies for
nonnaturalists. Either they (1) solely rely on the phenomenological
perspective, or (2) they take into account, and try to reconcile, both
perspectives. The first strategy falls prey to the Challenge from Lost Perspective.
Disregarding the external perspective in one’s (metaphysical)
interpretations of ethical deliberation is methodologically
unreasonable. Moreover, any purely phenomenology-based attempt
to warrant the exclusion of external evidence just moves the bump in the
rug. So, here is the big-picture conclusion: If nonnaturalists want to
go with the first strategy, they first have to justify the
legitimacy of this strategy—but this can only be done by taking the
second strategy. Thus, nonnaturalists must move beyond a purely
phenomenology-based strategy in any case. They must, on pain of
methodological unreasonableness, embrace the external perspective.
However, embracing the external perspective constitutes something
close to a paradigm shift for nonnaturalists. As far as I am aware, the
most prominent positive arguments for nonnaturalism are versions of the
argument from ethical phenomenology. They all maintain, in one way or
another, that some part of ethical phenomenology is best explained by
the existence of nonnatural ethical entities. This raises what I take to
be the million-dollar question for nonnaturalists: Is there a way to
legitimize the argument from ethical phenomenology that takes into
account both perspectives?
Let me say this much here: I believe there is good reason why
nonnaturalists traditionally fend off the relevance of the external
perspective in metaethics. If this dam broke, an entire ocean of
external, empirical evidence concerning, say, the evolutionary function
of deliberation or the origins of ethical intuitions would suddenly have
to be weighed in. All of this poses an obvious threat to the
nonnaturalist project: It may seem rather unlikely that the existence of
nonnatural entities will turn out to remain a better
explanation of ethical phenomenology than some externally
and internally informed account devoid of such entities. This partly explains, I think, the
typical nonnaturalist reluctance to acknowledge the external perspective
as relevant for metaethical theorizing. But if our considerations are
correct, nonnaturalists do not have much choice; they must overcome this
reluctance.
Conclusion
Nonnaturalists believe that ethical thought and talk involve (robust
or not-so-robust) nonnatural ethical entities. In this paper, we have
focused on the most prevalent positive argument for this view, the
argument from ethical phenomenology. According to it, the claim that
some ethical entities are nonnatural is part of the best explanation of
why ethical phenomenology is the way it is. Our main conclusion is that
the argument is methodologically unreasonable.
We started by stating the goals of metaethical investigations. These
investigations try to explain how ethical deliberation—and what, if
anything, it is distinctively about—fits into reality. We then argued,
quite generally, that investigations of mental processes should take
into account, and try to reconcile, both the internal (phenomenological)
and the external (broadly: scientific) perspectives. This, we claimed,
is where the argument from ethical phenomenology fails: It draws
metaphysical conclusions that are solely based on internal,
phenomenological observations. The argument, in other words, blinds out
the external perspective. Hence our main challenge:
Challenge from Lost
Perspective.
Proponents of the argument from ethical phenomenology must tell
us why the external perspective on ethical thought and talk does not
need to be taken into account before they conclude, on solely
phenomenological grounds, that ethical thought and talk are about
nonnatural entities.
In order to meet this challenge, we said, nonnaturalists must provide
an independent argument for the irrelevance of the external perspective.
We discussed one strategy to this effect that involves the just too
different intuition. We rejected this strategy for two reasons. The
(maybe) more important one was that the just too different intuition
cannot provide us with an independent argument for the
irrelevance of the external perspective because any argument based on it
would just be another instance of the argument from ethical
phenomenology.
Our big-picture conclusion was that nonnaturalists must move away
from a purely phenomenology-based strategy. Such strategies are
methodologically unreasonable because they do not take into account the
external perspective; they are unreasonable, that is, unless we
already knew that the external perspective is irrelevant for metaethical
theorizing. However, to establish that, nonnaturalists would
have to, well, move beyond a purely phenomenology-based strategy.
Otherwise, they would be arguing in circles, begging the question
against those who believe that the external perspective is
relevant for metaethical theorizing.
The big-picture conclusion is especially interesting once we
acknowledge that most of nonnaturalism’s supportive considerations are
entirely phenomenology-based. What exactly this
means for the prospects of nonnaturalism is a topic for another
occasion. I do think, however, that the loss of the argument from
ethical phenomenology leads to a significant decrease in plausibility
points—at least as long as nonnaturalists do not defend their approach
in a way that isn’t question-begging on the methodological level.
One final question: Could nonnaturalists reject the Challenge from Lost Perspective as
illegitimate? I don’t think so. The challenge represents a hard-to-doubt
methodological idea: When starting to investigate how any
mental process—and what this mental process is distinctively about—fits
into reality, we should be open to all kinds of evidence, external and
internal. We should not prematurely, that is, without further
argument, blind out or devaluate a whole
perspective on the mental process we are interested in—especially so if
this perspective has proven highly resourceful in the context of other
mental processes. Ultimately, the best account of the nature of ethical
deliberation will be one that hasn’t lost perspective.
Acknowledgements
On the journey that was this paper, many people helped me say more or
less plausible things more clearly. I would like to thank Dorothea
Debus, Christoph Halbig, Thorsten Helfer, Stefan Riedener, Jacob
Rosenthal, Peter Stemmer, Fabian Stöhr, Felix Timmermann, Pekka
Väyrynen, and Christian Wendelborn for comments and conversations. I
also profited from discussions with audiences at Davis (CA), Konstanz,
Saarbrücken, and Zurich. Special thanks to David Copp, who not only
embodied the ideal standards of being an academic host during my
research stay at the University of Davis in 2019 but also turned out a
pleasant and engaging academic guest when I invited him to Konstanz in
return. I am, once again, grateful to the Zukunftskolleg Konstanz for
the opportunity to participate in its terrific mentorship program. And,
finally, I am thankful that several anonymous referees from
Dialectica, JESP, and the Journal of Ethics
worked with me on a paper that, maybe a bit unfairly, is now published
under the name of a sole author.