Skip To Content
Cookies help us deliver our services. By using our services, you agree to our use of cookies.
Dialectica 75(2)

Dispositions and Token Identity

Beta version. This is a page made for testing purposes. For the official version of the article, please visit to OJS webpage at https://dialectica.philosophie.ch/.
    Abstract

    What is the relationship between dispositions and their categorical bases? Those who answer “identity” bear the burden of accounting for multiple realisation. According to orthodoxy, multiple realisability is a distinctively type-type phenomenon, and hence is unproblematic for token-token identifications. In this paper plurally realised dispositions are presented. It is argued that plural realisation is as problematic for the token-token identity theorist as standard type-type multiple realisation is for the type-type identity theorist. As an upshot, retreats to token identity in response to the problem of multiple realisability are shown to be dialectically inert, and alternative responses are corroborated.

    1 The Identity Theory

    What is the relationship between dispositions and categorical properties, for instance fragility and molecular structure, or belief and states of the brain? According to

    The Identity Theory. Each dispositional property is identical to some categorical property.1

    What are dispositions, and the categorical properties they are to be identified with? Standardly, both categories are ostensively defined. Fragility, flammability, mass, charge, and the like—these are the dispositions. Categorical properties include geometric properties, such as sphericity and squareness, and microstructural properties, such as being composed of H\(_2\)O or atomic lattices.2

    How do dispositional and categorical properties differ? Whilst there does appear to be some difference between the two, that difference is notoriously elusive. In fact, reflection on usage reveals a range of ways the distinction has been drawn. Let me name a few.

    The first is ontological. On this approach dispositional and categorical properties form distinct categories of existents (Ford 2012; Contessa 2019; Tugby 2020; Azzano 2021). Dispositions are properties with modally fixed causal profiles. In contrast, categorical properties have causal profiles that are modally variant (Bird 2016, sec. 2.2). Some reserve the terms “power” and “quiddity” for this distinction which is, I think, a sensible approach. Importantly, on this view “categorical” simply means “non-dispositional”. Evidently if that is what the identity theorist intends their theory is stillborn. But it seems clear they have no such distinction in mind. Even if all properties are powers, or if there are quiddities also, whether dispositions are identical to certain categorical properties remains an open question. To grant the identity theorist the fair trial they deserve, then, we must seek an alternative criterion.

    The second is semantic. On this view the distinction lies not between properties but predicates (Quine 1974, 11; Armstrong 1999; Shoemaker 1980). More precisely, categorical and dispositional predicates differ in their intensions i.e., their conditions of application. In particular, the intensions of dispositional but not categorical concepts make essential reference to the ascribed property’s effects. For example, the intension of “fragility” may be thought to make essential reference to breaking, smashing, or cracking. In contrast, whilst “being spherical” may be associated with certain effects, such as rolling or fitting in other shaped crevices and holes, the concept is not defined in terms of them. Put another way: only dispositional predicates are defined in terms of their manifestations.

    The third is epistemological.3 On this view dispositions differ from categorical properties in their apparent conditions of (non-inferential) perceptual knowability.4 Whilst dispositional properties appear to be perceptually knowable only by witness of their manifestations, categorical properties appear to be so knowable throughout the persistence of their instantiation. In a sense, dispositions are the apparently “hidden” or “inconspicuous” properties of objects and contrast with their relatively “conspicuous” categorical cousins. The dual notions of “dispositional” and “categorical”, on this view, denote the respective presence and absence of an apparent kind of perceptual concealment. Dispositions are the apparently perceptually inconspicuous persisting properties borne by objects. Categorical properties are unlike dispositions in that they do not appear to lie latent. It is this concealment, perhaps, that gives dispositions their distinctively “spooky” flavour and which moves us, as Goodman (1955) wrote, to bring them down to earth.5

    For present purposes we needn’t commit to either the semantic or the epistemological view. To investigate the identity theorist’s dialectic we need only grant that some plausible distinction exists. And so long as we are concerned only with the internal dialectic of their theory, we must. Furthermore, if we focus on paradigmatic examples the exact nature of the distinction will not affect the arguments that follow. Hence, for the purposes of evaluating the retreat from type-type to token-token identity theories I’ll assume there is some plausible distinction available to the identity theorist.

    2 The Argument from Causal Roles

    Why accept The Identity Theory? One influential argument employs the

    Causal Identity Principle. Two properties \(P\), \(P'\) are the same property just in case \(P\) and \(P'\) bestow the same total causal role \(R\) to their bearers.

    The Causal Identity Principle is Eleatic in spirit: it is causal efficacy that gives a property its ontic bite. But the principle goes further. Causal efficacy is not merely the mark of the sparse, but properties are individuated by the causal roles they bestow. The precise nature of a property’s causal profile is what makes it the very property that it is, and that which distinguishes it from all distinct properties.

    What are causal roles, and what is it to bestow them? Whilst this question is hardly straightforward, for present purposes we may bruit a rough view. For a property \(P\) to bestow a causal role \(R\) to some bearer \(x\) is for \(x\) to bear \(R\) in virtue of instantiating \(P\). Causal roles themselves we may think of as sets of possible causal contributions. A property \(P\) bestows a causal contribution at a case \(\alpha\) just in case \(P\) is causally efficacious in \(\alpha\).6 For instance, if a force \(F\) is exerted on a rubber band in \(\alpha\) which as a result deforms reversibly then the band’s elasticity bestows a causal contribution at \(\alpha\). On the precise nature of being causally efficacious we may remain neutral, saying only that \(P\) is efficacious with respect to some effect \(e\) just in case \(e\) occurs in virtue of the instantiation of \(P\). A property’s total causal role \(R\) is the set of all causal roles \(P\) bestows. According to this criterion, since the causal contributions bestowed by “being water” are the same as those bestowed by “being H\(_2\)O” the properties are identical. In contrast, since the causal contributions bestowed by “being flammable” and “being cube-shaped” differ the properties are distinct.

    Inquiry informs us that when a dispositional property manifests, certain categorical properties bestow causal contributions to that manifestation. When a disposition has some categorical property that bestows a causal contribution to its manifestations, that property is said to be its causal basis. For instance, the causal basis of the band’s elasticity is its possessing certain polymer chains which are causally efficacious in its reversely deforming. With such discoveries to hand, the causal identity principle may be employed in an argument to The Identity Theory.7 The identification holds between dispositional properties and their categorical causal bases. Letting “D” denote dispositional properties and “C” categorical causal bases, it runs as follows:

    (1) For all \(D\), there is some \(R\) such that \(D\) bestows \(R\).

    (2) For all \(D\), there exists some \(C\) such that if \(D\) bestows \(R\), \(C\) bestows \(R\).

    (3) If \(D\) bestows \(R\) and \(C\) bestows \(R\), then \(D\) = \(C\).

    (C) For all \(D\), there exists some \(C\) such that \(D\) = \(C\).

    To clarify, consider elasticity. Elasticity bestows a causal contribution to its bearers: elastic objects deform reversibly under stress. But that very same causal contribution is bestowed by the property of having polymer chains. Thus, by the right-to-left of the Causal Identity Principle, elasticity is identical to the property of having polymer chains. Since similar arguments may be run for all dispositional properties, we may identify dispositions and their categorical causal bases.

    3 Distinct Realisation

    The first two premises are vulnerable to attack. It has been argued that 1 is false since dispositions are not causally efficacious (Prior, Pargetter and Jackson 1982; Rundle 1997). It has been argued that 2 is false since some have no categorical grounds.8 In this paper, though, I wish to focus on a different, familiar worry: dispositions admit of multiple realisation, or to be more precise:

    Distinct Realisation. A property \(P\) is distinctly realised just in case there exist two distinct entities, \(x\), \(y\), such that \(Px\) and the causal basis for \(Px\) is \(C_1\), and \(Py\) and the causal basis for \(Py\) is \(C_2\), such that \(C_1 \neq C_2\).

    Consider flammability. In safety matches the causal basis of the property of being flammable is the property of having potassium chlorate, but in other matches the flammability is based by distinct chemicals. In non-safety matches, for example, phosphorus sesquisulfide is typically used.9 Similarly, an elastic metal may be elastic in virtue of its possessing not polymer chains but atomic lattices.

    From the existence of distinct realisation, the transitivity of identity, and the right-to-left of the Causal Identity Principle, a reductio that threatens The Identity Theory may be run. It takes the following form:

    (A1) If \(P\) bestows \(R\) and \(P'\) bestows \(R\), then \(P = P'\)

    (A2) \(D\) bestows \(R\), and \(R\) is bestowed by \(C_1\)

    (A3) \(D\) bestows \(R\), and \(R\) is bestowed by \(C_2\)

    (A4) \(C_1 \neq C_2\)

    (1) \(D = C_1\) (A1, A2)

    (2) \(D = C_2\) (A1, A3)

    (3) \(C_1 = C_2\) (1, 2, transitivity of “=”)

    (4) (\(C_1 = C_2\)) \(\wedge\) (\(C_1 \neq C_2\)) (A4, 3)

    Let’s walk it through.10 We start with the right-to-left of the Causal Identity Principle (A1). Next we consider two objects that possess the same type of disposition but distinct categorical realisers: perhaps an elastic band and an elastic metal rod. The causal basis of elasticity in the rubber band is its possession of polymer chains (A2), but in the rod the basis is its possession of an atomic lattices (A3). Moreover, we know that the possession of an atomic lattice is a distinct property from the possession of polymer chains (A4). Since two properties are identical if they bestow the same causal role, it follows that elasticity is identical to the possession of polymer chains (1). But it also follows that elasticity is identical to the possession of atomic lattices (2). By the transitivity of identity, the possession of polymer chains is identical to the possession of atomic lattices (3). But ex hypothesi the possession of polymer chains and the possession of atomic lattices are non-identical properties. Absurdity is now revealed: we have generated a contradiction (4).11

    4 The Token Retreat

    Faced with distinct realisation, what’s an identity theorist to do? At first blush it is not tempting to reject any assumption. But since most are unwilling to deny A1, and A4 can hardly be doubted, A2 and A3 are the usual suspects. But on what grounds are they to be denied? In what follows I consider two options.

    The first is to deny the datum: there is no distinct realisation. This will usually be motivated by the claim that such dispositions are not sufficiently sparse. One may, for instance, hold that there are identities between dispositions and their categorical bases only at the fundamental level (Bird 2007). Alternatively, one may accept macro-level dispositions but, like Heil (2004, 246–247), argue that the appearance of distinct realisation derives from the fact that we have a “range of similar properties all satisfying a single, moderately imprecise predicate”.12 Word making is not world making: there are many kinds of fragility, each of which is not distinctly realised.13

    Consider how this affects A2 and A3. Since there are two similar though distinct causal roles we should reformulate the assumptions as follows:

    (A2*) \(D\) bestows \(R_1\), and \(R_1\) is bestowed by \(C_1\)

    (A3*) \(D\) bestows \(R_2\), and \(R_2\) is bestowed by \(C_2\)

    But inconsistencies lurk. For now \(D\) bestows two distinct causal roles—by the Causal Identity Principle \(D \neq D\)! Thus really they should be formalised as:

    (A2**) \(D_1\) bestows \(R_1\), and \(R_1\) is bestowed by \(C_1\)

    (A3**) \(D_2\) bestows \(R_2\), and \(R_2\) is bestowed by \(C_2\)

    and now the purported distinct realisation has been explained away. The elasticity of rubber bands is identical to the property of having polymer chains, the elasticity of metal rods is identical to the property of having atomic lattices. But since elasticity\(_1 \neq\) elasticity\(_2\), contradiction is avoided.

    Now, although I am sympathetic to this approach, in what follows I will assume that distinct realisation is no phoney phenomenon. And that is for the purpose of evaluating the second option, which takes multiple realisation at face value. This is taking the token identity retreat. Here are two philosophers doing just that:

    The monist wants to say that there is just one attribute of \(x\), or state that \(x\) is in, that makes it true of \(x\) that \(Dx\) and that \(Cx\). This requirement can be satisfied even if the extensions of D and C do not coincide. Thus there need not be an identity of universals for monism. [E]ach instance of a disposition is identical to some instance of a categorical base [this] amounts to a token-token identity theory. […] This means that the argument from variable realization is disarmed […] the same move, to token-token identities, is available for dispositions in response to the variable realization argument.14 (Mumford 1998, 159–161)

    But I did miss something important, though. If the mental is nothing but that which plays a certain causal role […] then there is the possibility, which may even be an empirical possibility that the total causal role of tokens of the same mental type should be filled by tokens of significantly different physical types. Instead of type-type identity, one might have no more than a mental type correlated with an indefinite disjunction of physical types [but] every mental token is a purely physical token.15 (Armstrong 1968, xv)

    As formulated, the argument requires that for all dispositional properties \(D\), there is some unique type of categorical property \(C\) such that for any \(D\)-instance \(Dx\), some \(C\)-instance \(Cx\) is responsible for the causal contributions of \(Dx\). What cases of multiple realisability show is that, for many dispositions at least, there is no such type of categorical property. Different objects may bear the same dispositional property, despite the manifestations occurring in virtue of categorical properties of distinct types.16

    In contrast, a token identity theory makes no such demand. All that is required is that each token of a dispositional property \(Dx\) is identical to a token \(Cx\) of some property \(C\). \(C\) need not take a unique value. The rubber band’s elasticity is identical to its polymer chains, the metal rod’s elasticity is identical to its atomic lattice. But there is no requirement that the property of having atomic lattices is identical to the property of having polymer chains. Thus, whilst A2 and A3 are both false, it matters not.

    But if only tokens are identified, what of the types? Several alternative treatments are available. According to the first there are no types, only resemblance classes of individuals. All properties are particular; property “types” are merely classes of resembling property tokens. Categorical and dispositional properties, on this view, are simply distinct classes of property tokens or “tropes” individuated by the differing respects in which their members resemble. And so multiple realisability causes no sweat: a metal rod’s elasticity may be similar to the elasticities of all elastic objects, and its atomic lattices may be similar to all other atomic lattices, even if all of the former class do not resemble all of the latter. A token may resemble one class in certain respects, and another class in other respects, with no pain of contradiction.

    Again, although I am sympathetic to this approach the present arguments assume a different conception of tokens and types. Not for the reason that the conception is implausible, but simply because it is not relevant to the arguments that follow. For on this view there is in a sense no bona fide multiple realisability: the argument is avoided by banning types from our ontology. I have no doubt that an ontology which rejects universals but embraces tropes provides an alternative route to mere token identification. Let me be clear: if that is one’s motivation, so be it. If they feature in a fruitful metaphysics, let tropes bloom. The present gripe is not with endorsement of token identities per se; I am interested only in the adoption of token identity in response to the problem of distinct realisation.

    According to the second, which we saw Armstrong endorse above, the types are disjunctive. Elasticity is identical to the property of having either atomic lattices or polymer chains or so on and so on; possibly ad infinitum. According to the third the types are higher-order. Not “higher-order” as in “property of property”, but rather “the property of bearing a property of such-and-such sort”. For instance, being fragile may be thought of as having a property that bestows a certain subset of a causal role.

    With the disjunctive and higher-order views, though, a natural question may arise: wherein does motivation to endorse token identity lie? Answer: such views are notoriously difficult to square with the causal individuation of properties. Both higher-order and disjunctive properties appear entirely sterile: their causal powers seem preempted or excluded by the categorical properties that base them. And by the Eleatic principle, sterile properties are properties only in an abundant sense.

    But by identifying tokens—so the story goes—dispositions appear powerful again.17 If only dispositional types are shown to be sterile, what of it? It is property tokens that are standardly taken to be causally efficacious in any case (Campbell 1990). With identities maintained between token dispositions and their token categorical bases, no exclusion or preemption is achieved. And thus against the charge of inefficacy the identity theorist is in the clear.18

    But the Causal Identity Principle applies to types, not tokens. And the token retreat identifies tokens, not types. So how is identification to be achieved? Whilst properties are individuated in terms of their causal roles, property instances are typically not. There are, rather, two competing views on their individuation. According to the first property instances are individuated spatiotemporally. For instance, Schaffer (2001) argues that two property instances \(Px\), \(P'y\) are the same property instance just in case \(Px\) and \(P'y\) are compresent and maximally resemble. Alternatively, tokens may be taken to admit of brute individuation.

    This debate, though, largely takes place amongst those who embrace tropes, on whom there is an onus to provide individuation. With that in mind, there seems no reason why the friend of universals cannot maintain that property instances admit of causal individuation. Property instances do bestow causal roles: token causal roles. A token causal role is obtained by restriction. We look not at the set of cases of causal contributions of the property across all instantiations, but only given some particular instantiation. For example, we might look at the set of cases of causal contributions this heat from this very stove might confer.

    But whilst appeal to causal roles may be necessary to individuate property instances it cannot be sufficient. For we must exclude scattered instances, such as a property instance of “red” belonging to both a ruby and a rose, and distinguish distinct property instances borne by the same object at distinct times, such as the distinct greens of a chameleon’s skin before and after changing to a vibrant orange. None of this is troublesome. We must simply provide two supplements. The first is that the instances are coinstantiated (i.e., borne by the same object), the second that they are concurrent (i.e., instantiated at the same time). Putting all of this together, we have the following criterion of property instance individuation:

    Token Causal Roles. Two property instances \(Px\), \(P'y\), are the same property instance just in case \(x\) = \(y\), \(Px\) is concurrent with \(P'y\), and \(Px\) and \(P'y\) bestow the same token causal role \(R\).

    With that to hand, an argument to the token identity theory can be run. Here it is:

    (1) For all \(Dx\), \(Dx\) bestows some token causal role \(R\).

    (2) For all \(Dx\) there exists some \(Cx\), such that \(Cx\) is concurrent with \(Dx\) and \(Cx\) bestows \(R\).

    (3) If \(Dx\) is concurrent with \(Cx\) and both \(Cx\) and \(Dx\) bestow \(R\), then \(Dx\) = \(Cx\).

    (C) For all \(Dx\), there exists some \(Cx\), such that \(Dx\) = \(Cx\).

    As before, the first two premises are vulnerable to attack. It has been argued that both are false, as property instances are not causally efficacious (Steward 1997). And if some dispositions have no categorical grounds, the second premise faces the same threat. But again, permit me to set these worries to one side. In what remains of this paper I will argue that the token retreat is ill-motivated. And that is because problematic multiple realisation is not a distinctively type-type phenomenon. There is problematic multiple realisation at the token level. The upshot is: if one is worried about multiple realisation, retreat to the token level is dialectically inert.

    5 Plural Realisation

    Some dispositional properties are not based by a unique token of any causally efficacious property. I call these plurally realised dispositions. Plural realisation should be contrasted with

    Variable Realisation. A property \(P\) is variably realised just in case there exists an entity \(x\), such that \(Px\) at \(t_1\) and \(t_2\), and the causal basis for \(Px\) at \(t_1\) is \(C_1\), but the causal basis for \(Px\) at \(t_2\) is \(C_2\), such that \(C_1 \neq C_2\).

    Variably realised properties are well discussed.19 Pereboom (2002) considers the realisation of a statue by distinct lumps of clay across time, whilst Hurley and Noë (2003) consider cases of neural plasticity where mental properties are based by changing neurological complexes. Similar cases are constructible for patently dispositional properties. Consider a vial containing the poisonous chemical DEATH\(_1\). Now let DEATH\(_1\) decompose into DEATH\(_2\) from \(t_1\) to \(t_2\). In such a case, the deadly disposition is variably realised across time.

    How troublesome is variable realisation for one who takes the token retreat? Quite, though non-fatal. The purported worry is that the persistence conditions of the properties come apart from those of the bases. But time-indexing the identity relation is the standard counter-move.20 Property tokens exist only at one moment, and so their identities hold only at one instant. DEATH\(_1\) is identical to the poisonousness at \(t_1\), and DEATH\(_2\) to the poisonousness at \(t_2\), but \(x\)’s poisonousness at \(t_1 \neq x\)’s poisonousness at \(t_2\). And without token persistence, no transitivity can be exploited. The upshot is: arguments from variable realisation lose their bite.

    Not all will agree.21 But even if one accepts property instance persistence, retreaters to token identity are still liable to balk. That properties maintain their identity through time does not rule out that in cases of variable realisation one property is lost, another gained. Consider a pill \(x\) composed of both some benign mixture and DEATH\(_1\). Now remove the DEATH\(_1\)\(x\) will lose its token disposition. Now consider \(x\) with the DEATH\(_1\) removed and add to it DEATH\(_2\). A token disposition (assuming no reactions take place) will be gained: it will become poisonous. Now put the cases together: let DEATH\(_1\) and DEATH\(_2\) be exchanged. Why should matters change? One token disposition should be lost, another gained. The identity theorist will maintain that no disposition outlasts the persistence of its base. Even granted that tokens persist, in cases of variable realisation it may be argued that the persistence conditions of disposition and base do not come apart.

    But there are cases that cannot be so readily dispensed with. And that is because such cases involve intra-object multiple realisation accompanied by no change in properties. I called this

    Plural Realisation. A property \(P\) is plurally realised just in case there exists an entity \(x\), such that \(Px\), and \(Px\) has two causal bases, \(C_1\), \(C_2\), such that \(C_1 \neq C_2\).22

    Plurally realised properties are ones which have more than one causal basis in the same object at the same time. For clarity, we should make a (non-exclusive) distinction between properties that are wholly plurally based, and those that are partially plurally based. Consider a lighter’s disposition to ignite once sparked. This disposition is based by both the fuel, the flint, and the sparker all at once. But each of these is individually insufficient to base the disposition. It is therefore partially but not wholly plurally based. If the disposition is to manifest, the three bases must act holus bolus.

    A property is wholly plurally realised, in contrast, when it has two or more distinct sufficient causal bases. Consider Mackie:

    Even in the same material, the same disposition may have more than one ground. A piece of cloth may absorb water in two ways, by the water being taken into the individual fibres and by its being held in spaces between the fibres: its absorbency then has two different bases, the molecular structure of the fibres and the larger-scale structure in which those fibres are spun and woven. (1973, 148)

    For another example, cigarette smoke has the disposition to damage the lungs once inhaled, but that disposition is based distinctly by a wide variety of chemicals present in the smoke’s composition. In fact, cases are constructible with the following straightforward recipe. First, take two cases of distinct realisation, where the properties are capable of being coinstantiated. Perhaps a poisonous vial \(y\) of DEATH\(_1\), and a distinct poisonous vial \(z\) of DEATH\(_2\). Next, simply coinstantiate the properties, as in:

    Overkill. A vial of poison \(x\) contains two deadly chemicals DEATH\(_1\) and DEATH\(_2\). Because of this \(x\) has the disposition to kill when ingested.

    And voilá! A case of token multiple realisation has been constructed. In Overkill the mixture’s poisonousness is based twice-over in the same object. As such the disposition is multiply realised at the token level. And, as I will now show, plurally realised dispositions with distinct whole bases, such as the vial’s poisonousness in Overkill, are as problematic for the token identity theorist as distinctly realised dispositions are for the type identity theorist.

    The argument now begins. From the existence of plural realisation, the right-to-left of Token Causal Roles, and the transitivity of identity, a formally analogous reductio may be run. It takes the following form:

    (A5) If \(Px\) and \(P'x\) are concurrent and bestow the same token causal role \(R\), then \(Px\) = \(P'x\)

    (A6) \(Dx\) and \(C_1x\) are concurrent and bestow \(R\)

    (A7) \(Dx\) and \(C_2x\) are concurrent and bestow \(R\)

    (A8) \(C_1x \neq C_2x\)

    (5) \(Dx\) = \(C_1x\) (A5, A6)

    (6) \(Dx\) = \(C_2x\) (A5, A7)

    (7) \(C_1x\) = \(C_2x\) (5, 6, transitivity of “=”)

    (8) (\(C_1x\) = \(C_2x\)) \(\wedge\) (\(C_1x \neq C_2x\)) (A8, 7)

    Again we’ll walk it through. We start with the right-to-left of Token Causal Roles (A5). Then we note that \(x\)’s poisonousness is concurrent with \(x\)’s being composed of DEATH\(_1\), and both occupy the same token causal role (A6). Next we note that \(x\)’s poisonousness is concurrent with \(x\)’s being composed of DEATH\(_2\), and both occupy the same token causal role (A7). Finally, we know that DEATH\(_1 \neq\) DEATH\(_2\) (A8). It follows that \(x\)’s poisonousness = DEATH\(_1\) (5). But it also follows that \(x\)’s poisonousness = DEATH\(_2\) (6). By the transitivity of identity, DEATH\(_1\) = DEATH\(_2\) (7). Absurdity is again revealed: we have generated a contradiction (8).

    Crucially, the contradiction is derived from premises that involve token, not type identifications.

    6 Responses and Replies

    I have argued that the token retreat offers no solace from the problem of multiple realisability. How might the token identity theorist respond? In what remains I consider three responses. My strategy for dealing with them is as follows. I will argue that each faces an unpalatable disjunction: either (1) that response can be shown to fail, or (2) is available at the level of types.23 The upshot of (1) is that multiple realisation has not been avoided. The upshot of (2) is that the token retreat is robbed of its dialectical force.

    The first, and no doubt the most natural response, is that the basis in Overkill is complex. It may be thought, for example, that the disposition is identical to the conjunctional property (DEATH\(_1\) & DEATH\(_2\)).24 Why so? One reason would be that both DEATH\(_1\) and DEATH\(_2\) share the dirty work when the poisonousness manifests. They together occupy the relevant token causal role. They are causally efficacious both at once.

    This line of thought is convincing, but misleadingly so. It seems to have force due to the mistaken assumption that the total causal role bestowed by the disposition must be identical to that bestowed by the conjunction of the chemicals. The assumption is false: there are some plurally realised dispositions where the conjunction of that disposition’s bases bears a distinct token causal role from the disposition itself.

    Consider what we may call disjunctively realised dispositions. A disposition \(Dx\) is disjunctively realised just in case it has two bases \(C_1x\), \(C_2x\), such that the manifestations of \(Dx\) in some cases occur in virtue of \(C_1x\), and not \(C_2x\), in other cases in virtue of \(C_2x\) and not \(C_1x\), and in all other cases (if any remain) by (\(C_1x\) & \(C_2x\)). Disjunctive realisation is possible because distinct bases of the same dispositional property may differ in their conditions of masking, i.e., the conditions under which the basis is rendered inefficacious.25

    For example, suppose that some humans are perfectly resistant to DEATH\(_1\) but not DEATH\(_2\), whilst others are perfectly resistant to DEATH\(_2\) but not DEATH\(_1\). Now consider:

    Resistance-1. Jones ingests \(x\). Jones is perfectly resistant to DEATH\(_1\). Unfortunately Jones is not at all resistant to DEATH\(_2\), and thus as a result of ingesting \(x\) Jones dies.

    Resistance-2. Smith ingests \(x\). Smith is perfectly resistant to DEATH\(_2\). Unfortunately, Smith is not at all resistant to DEATH\(_1\), and thus as a result of ingesting \(x\) Smith dies.

    Suppose, as our responder would have us believe, that in Resistance-1 and Resistance-2 the vial’s poisonousness is identical to the conjunctional property (DEATH\(_1\) & DEATH\(_2\)). From this we may show what we know to be false: that both chemicals are causally efficacious in the death of Smith and the death of Jones.

    The conclusion is a consequence of two principles. The first is a straightforward consequence of Token Causal Roles. I call this the

    Identity of Causes. If \(Px\) bestows a causal contribution \(c\) in \(\alpha\), and \(Px\) = \(P'x\), then \(P'x\) bestows \(c\) in \(\alpha\).

    The principle follows because token causal roles are sets of possible causal contributions. If two properties share causal roles they must share all of their possible causal contributions. So if a property bestows a causal contribution \(c\), and is identical to some other property, that other property must also bestow \(c\).

    The second is not a consequence of Token Causal Roles but is independently plausible. I call this

    Conjunctional Causes. If (\(Px\) & \(P'x\)) bestows a causal contribution \(c\) in \(\alpha\), then \(Px\) bestows part of \(c\) in \(\alpha\) and \(P'x\) bestows part of \(c\) in \(\alpha\).

    This principle simply states that whenever a conjunctional property bestows a causal contribution \(c\) both conjuncts bestow some part of \(c\). My reasons for accepting Token Causal Roles are broadly Eleatic. We should accept that a conjunctional property bestowed a contribution only if both conjuncts had some causal stake in the game. Consider an object \(o\) with two properties: \(o\) is round and red. Now suppose the conjunction of the two properties is causally efficacious in some case \(\alpha\), perhaps by contributing to the opening of a door that has been designed to open only in the presence of round and red objects. Now in such a case we should say, given that the conjunctional property bestows a causal contribution, each of the conjuncts bestows some part of that causal contribution. In contrast, now suppose the door is primed only to open in the presence of red objects, no matter their shape. If the roundness makes no causal contribution to its opening in \(\alpha\), then the conjunction of its roundness and redness does not bestow a causal contribution in \(\alpha\). The causal contribution is bestowed merely from one conjunct.

    We are now in a position to reject the response. For suppose, as the respondent has claimed, that the vial’s poisonousness is identical to the conjunctional property (DEATH\(_1\) & DEATH\(_2\)). Since the vial’s poisonousness is causally efficacious in both cases, by Conjunctional Causes it follows that both DEATH\(_1\) bestows a causal contribution to the death of Jones, and DEATH\(_2\) bestows a causal contribution to the death of Smith. But ex hypothesi Jones is perfectly resistant to DEATH\(_1\), and Smith to DEATH\(_2\), thus the chemicals do not bestow the relevant causal contributions. We have proven what we know to be false. The reply must be denied.26

    Conjunctional won’t work; might disjunctional do the trick? Not obviously, for even setting aside the shameful status of disjunctive properties, the problem of causal exclusion re-arises.27 Just as with disjunctive types disjunctive tokens have nothing to contribute: their contributions are given by their disjuncts alone. And without causal efficacy no identification can be achieved, at least not by appeal to sameness of causal role.

    And worse still, once disjunctive tokens have been admitted motivation to move to the token level is lost. For if one is prepared to accept disjunctive tokens, why not disjunctive types? If one is content to retreat to the disjunctive in the face of plural realisation, why not in the face of distinct realisation? Simply put: to maintain disjunctive tokens whilst denying disjunctive types creates a dissonance entirely unwarranted by the presence of multiple realisability.

    The second response is that we should say that in Overkill there are two or more distinct tokens of the same dispositional type. This results in a commitment to what Armstrong (1978, 86) has called piling.28 Two property instances are piled just in case they (1) are of the same type and (2) are compresent (i.e., instantiated in the same object at the same time). Piling is standardly taken to be a serious bullet to bite. Those who embrace it do so tentatively, in accord only with the Eleatic principle.

    Fortunately enough we may dodge the issue entirely. Consider again the vial containing the deadly chemicals. Could the vial’s deadliness be piled? Not if the piled dispositions are identified with the distinct chemicals. This is due to what we may call the

    Relata of Identicals. If \(P\) = \(P'\), then \(P\) stands in some relation \(R\) iff. \(P'\) stands in \(R\).

    Since piling is a relation amongst properties, if there are two piled dispositions of the same type, one based by DEATH\(_1\) and the other by DEATH\(_2\), it should follow that DEATH\(_1\) and DEATH\(_2\) are piled. But the chemicals are not piled—they are of distinct types. By modus tollens, then, it cannot be said that the dispositions are of the same type.

    The third response is that disjunctive realisation involves multiple property instances of distinct types. Perhaps in Overkill the mixture has two distinct dispositions (one identical to DEATH\(_1\), the other to DEATH\(_2\)) or even three (the third being identical to the conjunction of the two). In response I offer an argument designed to show that there are at least some disjunctively realising bases that genuinely do base the same disposition. It runs as follows.

    The first premise is that dispositions are wholly individuated by their manifestations.29 Flammability is distinct from elasticity because flammability makes objects burn whilst elasticity makes objects reversibly deform.

    The second premise is that plurally realised properties may bear bases that differ with respect to their masking conditions, but not with respect to their manifestations. This is possible because two distinct properties may share a subset of their causal role relevant to the manifestation of some disposition, whilst bearing a distinct subset relevant to their masking.

    Perhaps the most vivid examples may be found not in deadly chemicals, but in deadly bacteria. E. coli (Escherichia coli) has a number of pathogenic strains including the shiga-toxin producing O104:H4. Like other co-evolved bacteria, E. coli strains change their properties of resistance over time—and thus the conditions under which their deadly disposition is masked. This may be done in several distinct ways: bacteria may develop the capacity to “pump out” or neutralise antibiotics, or they may produce subtle changes in their binding sites. Consider now a vial containing several shiga-toxin producing strains that base a deadly disposition. The manifestations of the various strains may be identical (i.e., perfectly similar)—and thus by the criterion of manifestation individuation the vial has only one deadly disposition. Nevertheless, the masking conditions of the individual strains may vary.

    The conclusion is that some distinct disjunctively realisable properties base the very same dispositional property.

    I anticipate one final worry. Perhaps one will hold that dispositions are individuated in part by their stimulus conditions, and are thus of a finer grain (Martin 2008, 89–91). This would make the first premise false. In which case there will be two tokens of distinct types even in the case of E. coli. But to this worry I say: now you have liberalised your ontology with properties of a finer grain why take the token retreat at all? The dissonance faced by the proponent of disjunctive tokens re-emerges: if one accepts distinct properties intra-object, why not inter-object also? If one chooses to fine-grain dispositional property instances to avoid plural realisation, why not fine-grain dispositional types to avoid distinct realisation? If the properties are of a finer grain, and hence distinct, there is no need to move from type to token identifications, since the response holds mutatis mutandis for the proponent of the type identity theory. To maintain the retreat one must offer an independent reason not to fine-grain dispositional types. The point I am making is not that such reasons cannot be given. My point is that if there are reasons, multiple realisation is not amongst them.

    In conclusion, I have argued that the token retreat offers no solace from the problem of multiple realisability. Whilst it may avoid distinct realisation, it cannot avoid plural realisation. Whilst there are responses to the latter that are not available to the former, each of those responses fails. The upshot is: there is no relevant difference between these types of multiple realisation vis-à-vis the identification of dispositions and their categorical bases. And as such, no ground is made by moving from the type to the token level.

    References

      Armstrong, David M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Reissued as Armstrong (2023).
      Armstrong, David M. 1973. Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511570827.
      Armstrong, David M. 1977. The Causal Theory of the Mind.” Neue Hefte für Philosophie 11: 82–95. Reprinted in Armstrong (1980, 16–31).
      Armstrong, David M. 1978. Nominalism & Realism: Universals and Scientific Realism, Volume I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
      Armstrong, David M. 1999. The Causal Theory of Properties: Properties according to Shoemaker, Ellis, and Others.” Philosophical Topics 26(1–2): 25–37, doi:10.5840/philtopics1999261/243.
      Armstrong, David M. 2005. Four Disputes About Properties.” Synthese 144(3): 309–320, doi:10.1007/s11229-005-5852-7.
      Audi, Paul. 2013. How to Rule Out Disjunctive Properties.” Noûs 47(4): 748–766, doi:10.1111/nous.12016.
      Azzano, Lorenzo. 2021. Dispositionality, Categoricity, and Where to Find Them.” Synthese 199(1-2): 2949–2976, doi:10.1007/s11229-020-02917-4.
      Bird, Alexander. 1998. Dispositions and Antidotes.” The Philosophical Quarterly 48(191): 227–234, doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00098.
      Bird, Alexander. 2007. Nature’s Metaphysics. Laws and Properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199227013.001.0001.
      Bird, Alexander. 2016. Overpowering: How the Powers Ontology Has Overreached Itself.” Mind 125(498): 341–383, doi:10.1093/mind/fzv207.
      Campbell, Keith. 1990. Abstract Particulars. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
      Contessa, Gabriele. 2019. Powerful Qualities or Pure Powers? Metaphysica 20(1): 5–33, doi:10.1515/mp-2019-2003.
      Davidson, Donald. 1970a. Mental Events.” in Experience and Theory, edited by Lawrence Foster and Joe William Swanson, pp. 79–101. Amherst, Massachusetts: University of Massachusetts Press. Reprinted in Davidson (1980, 207–225) and in Block (1980, 107–119).
      Davidson, Donald. 1970b. Events as Particulars.” Noûs 4(1): 25–32. Reprinted in Davidson (1980, 181–187), doi:10.2307/2214289.
      Ellis, Brian. 2002. The Philosophy of Nature – A Guide to the New Essentialism. Montréal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, doi:10.4324/9781315710624.
      Endicott, Ronald P. 1993. Species-Specific Properties and More Narrow Reductive Strategies.” Erkenntnis 38(3): 303–321, doi:10.1007/BF01128233.
      Feigl, Herbert, Scriven, Michael and Maxwell, Grover, eds. 1958. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume II: Concepts, Theories, and the Mind-Body Problem. Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.
      Ford, Sharon R. 2012. The Categorical-Dispositional Distinction.” in Properties, Powers and Structures. Issues in the Metaphysics of Realism, edited by Alexander Bird, Brian Ellis, and Howard Sankey, pp. 181–200. Routledge Studies in Metaphysics n. 5. New York: Routledge, doi:10.4324/9780203124482.
      Goodman, Nelson. 1955. Fact, Fiction and Forecast. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
      Heil, John. 1999. Multiple Realizability.” American Philosophical Quarterly 36(3): 189–208.
      Heil, John. 2003a. From an Ontological Point of View. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/0199259747.001.0001.
      Heil, John. 2003b. Multiply Realized Properties.” in Physicalism and Mental Causation. The Metaphysics of Mind and Action, edited by Sven Walter and Heinz-Dieter Heckmann, pp. 11–30. Exeter: Imprint Academic.
      Heil, John. 2004. Properties and Powers.” in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, volume I, edited by Dean W. Zimmerman, pp. 223–254. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780199267729.003.0009.
      Heil, John. 2011. Powers and the Realization Relation.” The Monist 94(1): 34–53, doi:10.5840/monist20119413.
      Heil, John and Robb, David. 2003. Mental Properties.” American Philosophical Quarterly 40(3): 175–196.
      Horgan, Terence E. 1993. Nonreductive Materialism and the Explanatory Autonomy of Psychology.” in Naturalism. A Critical Appraisal, edited by Steven J. Wagner and Richard Warner, pp. 295–320. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.
      Hurley, Susan L. and Noë, Alva. 2003. Neural Plasticity and Consciousness.” Biology and Philosophy 18(1): 131–168, doi:10.1023/A:1023308401356.
      Johnston, Mark. 1992. How to Speak of the Colors.” Philosophical Studies 68(3): 221–263, doi:10.1007/bf00694847.
      Kim, Jaegwon. 1992. Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52(2): 1–26, doi:10.2307/2107741.
      Lewis, David. 1966. An Argument for the Identity Theory.” The Journal of Philosophy 63(1): 17–25. Reprinted in Lewis (1983, 99–107), doi:10.2307/2024524.
      Lewis, David. 1979. Attitudes de dicto and de se.” The Philosophical Review 88(4): 513–543. Reprinted, with a postscript (lewis_dk:1983j?), in Lewis (1983, 133–156), doi:10.2307/2184843.
      Lewis, David. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
      Lowe, Edward Jonathan. 2011. How Not to Think of Powers: a Deconstruction of the ‘Dispositions and Conditionals’ Debate.” The Monist 94(1): 17–33, doi:10.5840/monist20119412.
      Martin, Charles Burton. 2008. The Mind in Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199234103.001.0001.
      Mellor, David Hugh. 2000. The Semantics and Ontology of Dispositions.” Mind 109(436): 757–780, doi:10.1093/mind/109.436.757.
      Molnar, George. 2003. Powers: A Study in Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited by Stephen Mumford, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199204175.001.0001.
      Mumford, Stephen. 1998. Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199259823.001.0001.
      Mumford, Stephen and Anjum, Rani Lill. 2011. Dispositional Modality.” in Lebenswelt und Wissenschaft, edited by Carl Friedrich Gethmann, pp. 468–484. Deutsches Jahrbuch Philosophie n. 2. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, doi:10.5840/djp2011231.
      Peacocke, Christopher. 1979. Holistic Explanation – Action, Space, Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
      Pereboom, Derk. 2002. Robust Nonreductive Materialism.” The Journal of Philosophy 99(10): 499–531, doi:10.2307/3655563.
      Place, Ullin Thomas. 1956. Is Consciousness a Brain-Process? The British Journal of Psychology 47: 44–60. Reprinted in Place (2004, 45–52), doi:10.1111/j.2044-8295.1956.tb00560.x.
      Prior, Elizabeth W., Pargetter, Robert and Jackson, Frank. 1982. Three Theses about Dispositions.” American Philosophical Quarterly 19(3): 251–257.
      Putnam, Hilary. 1967. The Mental Life of Some Machines.” in Intentionality, Minds, and Perception: Discussions on Contemporary Philosophy. A Symposium, edited by Hector-Neri Castañeda, pp. 177–200. Detroit, Maryland: Wayne State University Press. Reprinted in Putnam (1975).
      Quine, Willard van Orman. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press. New edition: Quine (2013).
      Quine, Willard van Orman. 1974. The Roots of Reference. LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court Publishing Co. The Paul Carus Lectures for 1963.
      Robb, David. 1997. The Properties of Mental Causation.” The Philosophical Quarterly 47(187): 178–194, doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00054.
      Robb, David. 2013. The Identity Theory as a Solution to the Exclusion Problem.” in Mental Causation and Ontology, edited by Sophie C. Gibb, Edward Jonathan Lowe, and Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson, pp. 215–232. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199603770.003.0010.
      Rundle, Bede. 1997. Mind in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198236917.001.0001.
      Schaffer, Jonathan. 2001. The Individuation of Tropes.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79(2): 247–257, doi:10.1080/713659225.
      Schaffer, Jonathan. 2004. Two Conceptions of Sparse Properties.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85(1): 92–102, doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.2004.00189.x.
      Shoemaker, Sydney S. 1980. Causality and Properties.” in Time and Cause: Essays Presented to Richard Taylor, edited by Peter van Inwagen, pp. 109–135. Philosophical Studies Series n. 19. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co. Reprinted in Shoemaker (2003, 206–233), doi:10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7.
      Shoemaker, Sydney S. 2007. Physical Realization. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199214396.001.0001.
      Shoemaker, Sydney S. 2013. Physical Realization without Preemption.” in Mental Causation and Ontology, edited by Sophie C. Gibb, Edward Jonathan Lowe, and Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson, pp. 35–57. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199603770.003.0003.
      Skiles, Alexander. 2016. In Defense of the Disjunctive.” Inquiry 59(5): 471–487, doi:10.1080/0020174X.2015.1122549.
      Smart, Jamieson John Carswell [Jack]. 1959. Sensations and Brain Processes.” The Philosophical Review 68(2): 141–156, doi:10.2307/2182164.
      Steward, Helen. 1997. The Ontology of Mind: Events, Processes, and States. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198250647.001.0001.
      Tugby, Matthew. 2020. Abduction and the Scientific Realist Case for Properties.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 98(1): 123–145, doi:10.1163/18756735-000112.
      Vetter, Barbara. 2014. Dispositions without Conditionals.” Mind 123(489): 129–156, doi:10.1093/mind/fzu032.
      Wilson, Jessica M. 2011. Non-Reductive Realization and the Powers-Based Subset Strategy.” The Monist 94(1): 121–154, doi:10.5840/monist20119417.

    Further References

      Armstrong, David M. 1980. The Nature of Mind, and other Essays. St. Lucia, Queensland: University of Queensland Press.
      Armstrong, David M. 2023. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge. With a new foreword by Peter Anstey, doi:10.4324/b23154.
      Block, Ned, ed. 1980. Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology. Volume I. Language and Thought. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.
      Davidson, Donald. 1980. Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Second, enl. edition: Davidson (2001).
      Davidson, Donald. 2001. Essays on Actions and Events. Philosophical Essays Volume 1. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Enlarged, doi:10.1093/0199246270.001.0001.
      Lewis, David. 1983. Philosophical Papers, Volume 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/0195032047.001.0001.
      Place, Ullin Thomas. 2004. Identifying the Mind. Selected Papers. Philosophy of Mind Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited by George Graham and Elizabeth R. Valentine, doi:10.1093/oso/9780195161373.001.0001.
      Putnam, Hilary. 1975. Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Volume 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511625251.
      Quine, Willard van Orman. 2013. Word and Object. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press. First edition: Quine (1960), doi:10.7551/mitpress/9636.001.0001.
      Shoemaker, Sydney S. 1984. Identity, Cause and Mind: Philosophical Essays. 1st ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Second, expanded edition: Shoemaker (2003).
      Shoemaker, Sydney S. 2003. Identity, Cause and Mind: Philosophical Essays. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Second, expanded edition of Shoemaker (1984), doi:10.1093/oso/9780199264698.001.0001.