Consider this case (derived from Krstić 2020, 758–759):
Pinartio. A vicious murderer, Tony, is hiding from
the police in Pinocchio’s house. In search of Tony, the police knock on
Pinocchio’s door asking whether Tony is hiding in his house. Pinocchio
wants to give Tony away but he is afraid that, if he gives any
indication of this to Tony, Tony will hurt him. Luckily, Pinocchio knows
both that the police know that his nose starts to grow at the very
instant he forms the intention to lie and that they know that he knows
that they know how his nose behaves, but that Tony does not know
anything about this. Therefore, he asserts “Tony definitely isn’t in my
house” to the police. Pinocchio does this not because he intends to
deceive the police in any sense (he doesn’t want them to think that he
is protecting a murderer), but rather because he intends to let them
know that Tony is in his house by having them recognize the
full content of his intention.
Pinocchio intends to cause the police to realize (i) that Tony is in
Pinocchio’s house, (ii) that Pinocchio is lying by saying that Tony is
not in Pinocchio’s house, and (iii) that he is lying because he intends
to cause them to deductively infer the relevant true proposition from
his assertion and the behaviour of his nose. Since he intends to cause
them to learn the whole truth—i.e., where Tony is, that he (Pinocchio)
is lying, and why—Pinocchio does not count as intending to deceive the
addressee and, because the nose is an indicator of lying rather than
uttering something he believes to be false, Pinocchio seems to be
genuinely lying.
Pinartio appears to be an excellent
counterexample to the view according to which intending to deceive is
necessary for lying. Mahon (2015) names this view
deceptionist. Some proponents of deceptionism are Davidson (1998),
Williams
(2002), Derrida
(2002), Faulkner (2007,
2013), Lackey (2013, 2019),
Keiser (2016),
Meibauer
(2014a, 2014b, 2016), Maitra (2018), and Harris
(forthcoming). Pinartio is a counterexample to this view
because Pinocchio does not intend to cause the police to believe what he
asserts (or to make them more confident in this proposition) and he does
not intend to cause them to believe that he believes what he asserts (or
to make them more confident in this proposition), which are the standard
ways of deceiving discussed in the literature on the nature of lies. In
fact, Pinocchio does not intend to mislead the police with respect to
anything or to conceal any information. He
is trying to help them.
Pinartio suggests that the
non-deceptionist analysis, according to which asserting what
you believe (or judge) is false is (necessary and) sufficient for lying,
is correct. Some proponents of the
non-deceptionist view are Aquinas (Summa Theologica, II-II,
Q.110, article 1), Johnson (1755a), Carson
(2006, 2010), Sørensen
(2007, 2010, 2022), Fallis
(2009, 2012, 2013, 2015), Saul (2012), Stokke
(2013, 2016, 2017, 2018), Rutschmann and Wiegmann
(2017), Krstić (2018, 2019,
2020), Marsili
(2021), Sneddon
(2021), and Michaelson and Stokke (2021).
And while Pinocchio’s lie is a so-called bald-faced lie, i.e., knowingly
undisguised lie, it is different from all other cases of bald-faced lies
in a very important way. Standardly, bald-faced lies involve situations
in which the liar believes that it is common knowledge that what the
liar says is false. The common knowledge bald-faced liar does
not intend to deceive their addressee because they think that the
addressee already knows the truth. Say that a gambler asserts to his
wife that he was not gambling when she caught him with the betting
tickets from that afternoon’s races (Arico and Fallis 2013); it seems
sensible to think that he did not try to make his wife believe him,
since he should think that she already knows everything.
However, the deceptionists promptly responded to the argument from
the existence of these bald-faced lies by saying that the proposed
examples (1) are either lies intended to deceive in some of the senses I
mentioned above or (2) are not genuine lies in the sense in which they
do not involve genuine assertions—and you need to assert in order to
lie. These replies do make the common
knowledge bald-faced lies much less effective. A desperate gambler may
hope that his lie could cause his wife to become slightly less confident
in her true belief and he could add that the ticket belongs to a friend.
Alternatively, it might be that, since he does not intend his wife to
believe him, the gambler does not assert what he says but rather merely
makes it look like he does; he could be playing a kind of a (language)
game, he could be doing something similar to acting or even to being
verbally aggressive (e.g.,
Keiser 2016; Maitra 2018; Harris forthcoming; Meibauer 2014a; against,
e.g., Marques 2020; Viebahn 2019; Marsili 2021).
These two general objections are well-known and, in one form or
another, they have been put forward in detail by many contemporary
philosophers (e.g.,
Faulkner 2007, 2013; Kenyon 2010; Lackey 2013, 2019; Meibauer 2014a,
2014b, 2016; Leland 2015; Dynel 2011, 2015; Hawley 2018; Keiser 2016;
Maitra 2018; Harris forthcoming). I do not intend to discuss
their application to common knowledge bald-faced lies for two reasons.
The first is that some replies already exist (e.g.,
Fallis 2015; Stokke 2017, 2018; Marques 2020; Viebahn 2019; Marsili
2021). The second, and more important, is that I designed cases
like Pinartio to avoid both deceptionist
objections. Pinartio involves what I named a “tell-tale
kind” bald-faced lie (Krstić 2020), in which the addressee
not only does not know the truth (no common knowledge) but rather
learns the truth by observing the behaviour of the
lie-disclosing sign and, vitally, Pinocchio intends this to
happen. He wants the police to deductively infer the truth from his
false assertion and the behaviour of his nose. Therefore, the lie is not
intended to deceive the addressee in any sense. Since it is clear that
the speaker does not intend to deceive, Pinartio seems to be
an importantly different counterexample to the deceptionist analysis of
lying; it gives us a new perspective on the issue and thus it opens the
door for a new and promising debate.
This paper is designed to fill this void and bring the debate
regarding lies and intending to deceive closer to a fruitful end. In
section 1, I argue that cases such as Pinartio are not uncontroversial but that
more convincing cases can be developed from them. In section 2, I discuss two objections to my argument. In
section 2.1, I reject the popular
objection according to which bald-faced lies are not genuine lies on the
count of them not involving genuine assertions. In section 2.2, I argue against the interpretation
that tell-tale liars (indirectly) assert not the literal meaning of the
descriptive sentence they utter but rather the proposition they want the
hearer to infer from their behaviour. In section 3, I conclude my argument.
Finding the Right Case
My original cases do avoid some standard objections but I see now
that they also generate new problems. In this section, I discuss these
problems and offer a case that avoids them. In the next section, I
discuss two further objections that arise.
In my analysis of Pinartio, I write:
The non-[deceptionist] definition counts this [Pinocchio saying “Tony
definitely isn’t in my house”] as lying because Pinocchio asserts what
he believes is false, I count this as lying because the nose grows, and
the [deceptionist] definition does not count this as lying because
Pinocchio does not intend to deceive his addressee notwithstanding the
fact that the nose indicates that Pinocchio is lying—this is
why (Pinartio) is a counterexample to the
[deceptionist] definition. [Krstić (2019), 653; italics added]
In short, I argue that Pinartio is a counterexample to the
deceptionist analysis because (i) Pinocchio does not intend to deceive
his addresses and (ii) the nose indicates that he is lying. Pinartio cannot be dismissed on the count
of it being a fairy-tale case. True, Pinocchio is a fictional character
and the situation I put him in is uncommon. However, this is not
relevant to the question under discussion. My main idea is to present a
situation in which a speaker believes (correctly or
incorrectly, it does not matter) that their lie will undoubtedly be
disclosed to the addressee and they use this circumstance to communicate
the truth. In real life, police may convince their suspect that their
lie detector makes no mistakes and there could be a real-life person who
mistakenly believes that they always blush when they lie, or that their
interlocutor can read their thoughts, or is skilled enough in detecting
lie-betraying cues. In Meet the Parents (Universal Pictures,
2000), Jack Byrnes convinces his future son-in-law, Greg Focker, that he
will unmistakably detect when Greg lies just by feeling Greg’s pulse. I
merely flesh this situation out using the character of Pinocchio as a
communicative device.
Moreover, the issue of whether the nose will grow or not is
irrelevant: the deceptionist definition assumes that the
intention to deceive is necessary for lying. If the nose does
not grow, Pinocchio will still lie; he will just fail to communicate the
truth. The examples are effective as long as (i) the liar
believes that something will show that he is lying and (ii) the
liar and their audience are in a standard context (i.e., unless some
further conditions apply) in which it is common ground that one asserts
what one says. Thus, even if Pinocchio misleads the police by asserting
what he says, this would be against his intention, which still sits
uneasily with the deceptionist analysis. Consider the following
case.
Artocchio. A vicious murderer, Tony, is hiding in
Artie’s house. The police come to question Artie about Tony’s
whereabouts but Artie is too afraid to tell them that Tony is right
here—Tony might hear him. Luckily enough, Artie believes that he blushes
only and always when he lies and that Tony does not know about this.
Artie decides to use this to let the police know the truth without
thereby alarming Tony. Therefore, he asserts “Tony is not in my
house” to them excepting that he will immediately start blushing, that
this will be a clear sign to the police that he is lying, and that they
will realise from this that Tony is in Artie’s house. Of
course, Artie blushes not because blushing is somehow connected to
whether he believes what he asserts but rather due to the highly
stressful situation he is in.
In Artocchio, Artie believes that there is a
perfectly reliable giveaway of lying and he intends to use it to cause
the police to infer the truth from his lie. Artie’s blushing is not a
real tell-tale sign of lying but it worked as one nonetheless.
Furthermore, Artie and the police are in a standard context, he thinks
that he will be understood as asserting what he says and they expect him
to assert what he says, and thus there seem to be no reasons to think
that he did not assert what he said. Importantly, Artie’s blushing is
not analogous to winking or finger-crossing: the function of winking is
set by a convention that is a part of common ground (the context is not
standard) and Artie’s blushing is not. Therefore, we should think that
Artie is understood as asserting what he says and his plan is not
unwise: if the police are sufficiently attentive to detail, they will
realise that he is lying and why he is lying. Nevertheless, there is an
important concern that Tony was intentionally caused to believe falsely
that Artie deceived the police. Tony was misled, that is; just as Artie
planned.
In Krstić (2019,
656), I argue that the issue of whether Artie intended to deceive
Tony is irrelevant for the question of whether lies must be aimed at
deceiving—since Artie was addressing the police, not Tony. However, it
may be that Artie was addressing Tony after all: Artie needed Tony to
hear what he is saying. Hence, Tony does appear to be Artie’s intended
hearer and, it seems to follow, Artie did intend to deceive someone by
lying—Tony. The conclusion that Artie intends to
deceive Tony by lying, however, does not follow. Tony expects and
coerces Artie to say to the police that Tony is not in Artie’s house and
Artie says this because he knows that Tony expects him to do it.
Therefore, Artie cannot reasonably intend to cause Tony to believe as
true a proposition for which Artie knows that Tony knows is false. Thus,
even if Artie addresses Tony, he cannot be lying to Tony in the
sense in which this requires intending to deceive him. In fact, he does
not seem to be lying to Tony at all: he just says what Tony wants him to
say. Say that a company manager orders
his assistant to present false data at the board meeting in exchange for
a promotion. This assistant will lie to other board members but not to
his boss. The same applies to Artie.
So, it seems as if Artie lies while not intending to deceive anyone
by asserting what he says. However, whether Artocchio is enough
to reject the deceptionist view depends on how broad our analysis of
lying is. On the view that one may lie only by asserting something one
believes is false, Artocchio vindicates the non-deceptionist
definition. However, broader analyses exist (see footnote 3) and so one may argue that Artie’s lie is
intended to deceive Tony—only in a sense that does not involve
asserting. Artie may, for instance, intend to deceive Tony by falsely
implicating that he led the police off Tony’s track. On this analysis,
then, Artie both counts as asserting what he says and as intending to
deceive by lying (i.e., by implicating false information to Tony).
Therefore, while Artocchio does appear to put reasonable
pressure on the deceptionist analysis, there still are some
controversies about it. Most of these controversies can be eliminated
with simple modifications. Consider the following case.
Witnessio. A gruesome murder happened in Artie’s
bar. The police do not know who did it but Artie knows that Tony did it.
Artie wants Tony off his back but he is afraid to testify against Tony.
Artie believes that he blushes always and only when he lies, he believes
that the police know this as well, and he decides to use this to let the
police know that Tony is the murderer without actually testifying
against him (thus avoiding the imminent retribution). Tony went to
Polly’s place to hide the murder weapon and Artie knows this. Therefore,
Artie says to the police “Maybe you could talk to Tony? A minute ago, he
rushed to Polly’s house regarding a matter of great urgency. Tony
definitely did not commit the crime.” Artie hopes that he will
start blushing while uttering the last sentence, that this will be a
clear sign to the police that he is lying, and that they will realise
from this that he wants to let them know both that Tony committed the
crime and where they can find him. Artie hopes that they will catch Tony
with the murder weapon.
Witnessio and Artocchio involve a
rather plausible idea that some people may think that something will
unmistakably show that they are lying and they are similar to the
context of two recent movies. The first is Knives Out
(Lionsgate, 2019) in which the character of a nurse, Marta Cabrera,
cannot lie without vomiting (“Just the thought of lying […] It makes me
puke,” she says), the detectives that are questioning her know this, she
knows that they know, and indeed she does vomit every time she lies. The
second is Meet the Parents (Universal Pictures, 2000), in which
Jack Byrnes convinces his future son-in-law, Greg Focker, that he will
unmistakably detect when Greg lies just by feeling Greg’s pulse (the
pulse is a lie-betraying sign). The main difference is that, on the one
side, Marta avoids lying by giving true but incomplete answers to
questions when asked and Greg simply goes for telling the truth,
whereas, on the other side, Artie comes up with a plan to make lemonade
when life gives him lemons: he decides to use what he thinks is his
otherwise unfortunate reaction to his advantage and cause the police to
learn the truth by lying to them. Another difference is that, if Artie
blushes at the right moment, this will be not because blushing is
somehow connected to whether he lies but rather because of the highly
stressful situation he is in.
In Witnessio, Tony did not end up with a false
belief; rather he was left without any belief regarding Artie’s
conversation with the police. More importantly, not only is Artie not
addressing Tony, he hopes that Tony never learns about the conversation.
Therefore, neither did Artie intend to deceive Tony, nor was he lying to
Tony. Even if one can lie by making false promises, implicatures, or
presuppositions, Artie does not lie to Tony in any of those senses; he
is not addressing Tony. While Artie does not lie intending to deceive
the police, misleading them about Tony’s whereabouts or Artie’s
intentions is possible in Witnessio (they do
not believe that Artie blushes always and only when he lies) but this is
irrelevant for our discussion. We are not analysing whether epistemic
harm will be caused but rather whether the liar intends to
cause it or whether he expects that he might cause it (see Krstić 2020, sec.
2.1) and Artie clearly lacks the intention to deceive them and he
does not expect them to end up misled (he believes that they will
understand why he blushes). Finally, because the belief that Artie
blushes always and only when he lies is not common ground between Artie
and the police, we cannot say that blushing implies that Artie does not
assert what he says.
Witnessio avoids the most obvious
objections, but it fails to avoid all objections. I anticipate two. The
first is that, because he does not intend to give the police a reason to
believe what he says, Artie does not assert what he says and thus does
not lie. The second is that Artie (indirectly) asserts the proposition
he intends the police to infer from his behaviour and the literal
meaning of the uttered proposition (“Tony committed the crime”) and,
because he believes this proposition to be true, he does not count as
lying. I will resolve these objections in turn.
Objections
Not an Assertion
According to one influential analysis of assertion (Gricean in
nature), I asserted that \(p\) by
uttering \(x\) if and only if I uttered
\(x\) intending to induce in you the
belief that \(p\) or give you grounds
for believing it by means of your recognition of the full content of my
intention (e.g.,
Bach and Harnish 1979; Récanati 1987; similarly, Peirce 1935; Grice
1989). Accounts of this sort are typically
called Gricean or Neo-Gricean, Keiser (2016) calls them
epistemic, and Harris (forthcoming) and Siebel (2020) call this
approach to communication intentionalism. I will refer to the
view as Neo-Gricean analysis of assertion.
According to one influential argument based on the Neo-Gricean
analysis of assertion, because he does not intend to give his
audience grounds for believing what he says because he says so, Artie
does not count as asserting what he says in Witnessio and
therefore—on the popular assumption that lies are a subset of
assertion—he does not lie (e.g.,
Chisholm and Feehan 1977; Meibauer 2014a, 2014b, 2016; Keiser 2016;
Harris forthcoming, 13, 15). That is to say, I assume that one
would object that, while there is nothing in the context that could
prevent Artie’s utterance to count as an assertion, Artie did not act on
an intention constitutive of asserting and this failure (rather
than pragmatic considerations or linguistic conventions) disqualifies
the utterance from counting as an assertion and a genuine lie (which
requires asserting what you say).
Many influential philosophers think that this is a very serious
problem for any non-deceptionist analysis of bald-faced lies. The idea
is that, because Neo-Griceans think that the ordinary language concept
of lying is too ambiguous, they are looking for a definition of lying
that fits neatly within their definition of assertion, which in turn
fits neatly within a relevant broader theory of speech acts and
communication. Therefore, they will maintain that bald-faced lies are
not genuine lies because they do not involve genuine assertions. While
Artie believes that his blushing signals that he is lying when he is
lying, his conception of lying is too broad and he does not intend to
lie in the relevant sense (which involves asserting what you say).
I will reject this objection in three steps, where each step gives my
argument a premise. In step 1, I argue (by analogy) that the argument
from the objection generates an unfalsifiable position. In step 2, I
argue that it entails that competent language users unreliably track
assertions, which is a very bold and empirically unsupported claim. The
first two steps only show that the objection is much less serious than
what initially seems; they do not show that it fails. The third step,
however, shows that the argument fails. In step 3, I argue that, if
understood as not allowing exceptions (such as bald-faced lies), the Neo-Gricean
analysis of assertion misclassifies some sincere assertions
as not assertions: some sincere asserters do not act on the intention to
give their hearers grounds for believing what they say. I conclude that,
considering steps 1–3, this specific argument claiming that bald-faced
lies are not genuine assertions fails. I now proceed to step 1.
In his Introductory Lectures on Psycho-analysis (1916–1917),
Freud defends his dream theory from the concern that dreams do not
reveal our unconscious mental life. His defence is strikingly similar to
the comeback presented above: he dismisses counterexamples by
reinterpreting them. The following is one such case.
A woman dreamer says: “Am I supposed to wish that my husband were
dead? Really that is outrageous nonsense! Not only is our married life
very happy, though perhaps you won’t believe that, but if he died I
should lose everything I possess in the world.” (Freud 1929, 121)
This woman directly challenges Freud’s diagnosis in the same way Witnessio challenges the deceptionist
account of lying (Artie thinks that he is lying; the woman thinks that
she wants her husband alive). Freud’s answer is very interesting.
Assuming that unconscious tendencies do exist in mental
life, the fact that the opposite tendencies predominate in conscious
life goes to prove nothing. […] What does it matter if
you [the woman] do find the results of dream-interpretation
unpleasant, or even mortifying and repulsive? “Ça n’empêche pas
d’exister” [“It doesn’t prevent things from existing”]. [Freud (1929), 122;
italics added]
Freud practically says that the woman incorrectly believes that she
does not want her husband dead because her desire is unconscious. This
reply raises two important problems (see Derksen 2001). According to the
reply, Freud’s theory is correct no matter what the woman says: the only
difference is in whether the desire is conscious or unconscious. A
theory defended in this way can never be disproved since any testimony
becomes evidence in support of it. Therefore, the reply makes Freud’s
position unfalsifiable; the first flaw. The second flaw is that the
comeback is viciously circular (i.e., it begs the question). Freud
correctly says “assuming that unconscious tendencies do exist
in mental life [i.e., that his theory is correct],” the fact that this
woman’s testimony contradicts his theory “goes to prove nothing.” But,
whether his theory is correct is exactly what is at stake. This
testimony is a counterexample to his theory and the theory cannot be
used as a reason to disregard it.
The argument to the conclusion that bald-faced lies do not involve
genuine assertions involves the same fallacious line of reasoning. This
is the analogy between the two replies: Freud says that, if the woman
concurs with his diagnosis, her desire is conscious and, if she denies
it, the desire is unconscious, she just thinks that she does not have
the desire. Analogously, according to the given argument, if speakers
intend to deceive by lying, then their lies involve genuine assertions
and, if they do not intend to deceive, then their “lies” do not involve
genuine assertions; these speakers just think that they are genuinely
lying.
And here is the immediate problem with this comeback: if we cannot
trust the speakers’ judgements as to whether they are lying or not, then
no testimony can be used as a counterexample to the given analysis of
assertion. Therefore, the reply causes the view to become unfalsifiable.
This reply uses the idea that intending to give grounds for beliefs is
necessary for asserting to discredit cases of bald-faced lies
but whether this intention really is necessary for asserting is exactly
what is at stake in this debate. Therefore, the reply begs the
question.
The circularity is actually very visible in this argument. What the
reply is actually saying is that the deceptionist definition of lying
fits neatly within the Neo-Gricean definition of assertion, which in
turn fits neatly within a relevant broader Gricean theory of speech acts
and communication, but this is the same theory. In effect, then, the
argument says that assuming that Neo-Griceanism is correct, the
fact that other people (e.g., Artie, Pinocchio, Marta) see bald-faced
lies as genuine lies goes to prove nothing; their testimonies do not
matter. This is not to say that Neo-Griceanism is incorrect but this
specific defence is problematic and, as philosophers, we should be
basing our views on good arguments. Therefore, because it is viciously
circular and unfalsifiable, this argument should not be accepted
unconditionally. I now proceed to argue that it also makes a very daring
claim; this is step 2 in my argument.
This dispute is not only about what people (Artie, Marta Cabrera,
etc.) recognize as lying but also about what they recognize as
asserting. Therefore, in discrediting bald-faced lies in this particular
way, one is not just saying that common folks have a broader conception
of lying, but also that they cannot recognize when a proposition is
being asserted. This strikes me as a rather bold
position, which is the second premise in my argument, step 2. In a
standard context, assertion simply seems to be a default interpretation
of a declarative sentence, and this view seems to be common ground in
the debate. Williamson (2000, 258), for
instance, writes: “In natural language, the default use of declarative
sentences is to make assertions.” That being said, even though the idea
is bold, it is not completely unwarranted. Consider the following
argument made by Keiser
(2016).
In The Godfather 2 (Paramount, 1974), “Frankie Five Angels”
Pantangelli is called in as a surprise witness in a Senate hearing
against the mob boss Michael Corleone but, to everyone’s utter shock, he
goes against the agreement and claims under oath that he has no
knowledge of any wrongdoings committed by Michael Corleone. Keiser (2016, 471)
argues that, since he does not intend to give his audience grounds for
believing what he says, Frankie does not assert what he says; rather, he
is playing a “courtroom [language] game,” a game in which a speaker can
avoid asserting what they say but still achieve a specific intended
effect (e.g., go for the record).
People standardly think that witnesses assert statements they make
while testifying under oath—witnesses assume many assertoric commitments
(they, e.g., guarantee that what they say is true)—and the terms “lying
on the stand” or “lying under oath” are standardly understood as lying
by asserting what the witness believes is false. According to Keiser,
however, Franky was just making a move in a courtroom game. If he lied,
this was not in the sense we are discussing here (it does not involve
the default use of a declarative sentence) and our intuitions about the
case are incorrect. Following this analysis of Frankie, one may
say that, while we may allow that common folk can recognize asserting in
standard contexts, the cases I discuss are all fictional and very
unusual (nose growing, blushing). Therefore, even if it is true that
people can reliably detect assertions in standard contexts, this is of
limited value for my argument.
Keiser does not offer an unreasonable interpretation of this
particular case, people’s intuition may go in the wrong direction in the
“courtroom” context, but the idea that bald-faced lies are not genuine
assertions is not only bold, it is also controversial. For one, choosing
Frankie to support a very general claim—namely, that
no bald-faced lie involves a genuine assertion—is rather
unfair: Frankie involves a specific, non-standard context that
allows Keiser to apply her “game” analogy but people predominantly lie
in standard contexts. Therefore, we cannot apply insights from Frankie
to all cases of bald-faced lying: the analogy breaks. People would have
been equally shocked if Frankie had said that he knew no Godfather in a
standard context far away from the courtroom (e.g., in a private
conversation), they would have been shocked because they would think
that he is lying, and Keiser’s argument would not apply here as easily
as in the courtroom context.
Gambler, for example, involves a standard context and there
are good reasons to say the same about Witnessio. After
all, Artie is not in a courtroom, and the police did not arrest him or
bring him in for questioning; they were just talking. Consider the
following combination of Gambler and Witnessio.
Gamblessio. Tony has a gambling addiction and Tony’s
wife, Carmela, knows this. Tony lies to Carmela by saying that he has
quit gambling and he makes Artie keep his betting ticket. However, Artie
accidentally drops it when he goes to Tony’s place to pick up a thing
and Carmella sees the ticket. Artie is worried about Tony but he does
not want to openly tell Carmela that Tony did not stop gambling; he does
not want to hurt Tony’s feelings by betraying his trust. However, Artie
believes that he blushes always and only when he lies, he believes that
Carmela knows this as well, and he decides to use this to let her know
that the ticket belongs to Tony without actually saying this out loud
(which would give him an excuse in front of Tony). Therefore, Artie says
to her “Don’t worry, Carmela, the ticket does not belong to Tony, it’s
mine” hoping that he will start to blush and that Carmela will infer
from this that Artie is lying, that the betting ticket is Tony’s, and
that Artie is trying to preserve everybody’s dignity by acting this way
(it’s a kind of a prosocial tell-tale sign bald-faced lie).
Gamblessio preserves the virtues of Witnessio while making the stakes lower.
Therefore, even though the position according to which our intuitions
about lying may be unreliable may make sense when applied to cases such
as Frankie, it fails to easily generalise to all cases of
bald-faced lying.
As I argued in step 2, the claim that no bald-faced lie is an
assertion is very bold: it entails that many people are not competent
speakers. Of course, there is nothing wrong with making bold claims
per se but, other things being equal, we should go for less
demanding claims. And other things are not equal: this bold argument not
only begs the question and generates an unfalsifiable position, it also
suffers from three additional problems. Two can be immediately noticed.
One problem is that this position cannot be easily generalised to all
cases of bald-faced lies. I discussed this problem here. It is not
really obvious that we can say that Artie and Carmela do not know what
it is to assert a proposition in the context of Gamblessio.
Another problem is that Artie and Pinocchio assert according to many
successful accounts of assertion and so we do not need to commit
ourselves to very demanding positions.
Other views will say that Artie and Pinocchio assert what they say
because they take themselves as being in a warranting context (Saul 2012), because
they propose that what they say be added to official common ground (Stalnaker
1984, 1999, 2002; Stokke 2013, 2016, 2017, 2018), because they
represent themselves as believing what they say (Black 1952;
Davidson 1998; Fallis 2013) and even as knowing what they say
(Unger
1975, 250–270; DeRose 2002, 185). They also count as asserting
what they say because they make many assertoric commitments: they
warrant the truth of what they say (Carson 2006, 2010),
they undertake the responsibility of justifying their assertion and what
follows from it (Brandom 1994, 173–175), they commit
themselves to act in accordance with what they say (Dummett 1981) or
that they will withdraw it if the proposition is shown to be untrue
(MacFarlane 2005;
similarly, Dummett 1991, 165), they commit themselves to the
truth of what they say (Marsili 2021; similarly,
Dummett 1981, 300), and so on.
With all of this in mind, while one need not think that
Neo-Griceanism delivers a failed analysis of assertion, one must wonder
whether making bold claims just to keep a particular interpretation of
Neo-Griceanism is justified. It may just be that Neo-Griceanism allows
for exceptions. If this is correct, we get to keep
both the Neo-Gricean analysis of assertion and the idea that some lies
not intended to deceive are genuine assertions. This is why, in my final
step 3, I argue that the intention to give grounds for believing what
you say cannot be necessary for asserting what you say; this is the
additional third problem this bold position faces. Consider a real-life
case involving a sincere speaker.
Arangio. Stephen Miller puts credence 0 in the
proposition that refugees benefit the American economy more than they
cost. Jennifer Arangio, a lower-level aide who has looked at the
relevant studies, has credence 1 that refugees benefit the American
economy more than they cost. Arangio is well aware that, whatever she
says, Miller’s credence in this proposition will not be shifted one bit.
Nevertheless, she tells Miller the truth and thereby risks her job.
Because she is well aware that, whatever she says, Miller’s credence
in the proposition will not be shifted one bit, Arangio cannot
reasonably intend to give Miller grounds for believing what she says
based on her say-so. Therefore, according to the given argument, because
she cannot rationally intend to give Miller grounds to believe what she
says, Arangio cannot rationally assert to Miller
a proposition she believes to be true. In other words, according to a
consistent application of the argument claiming that no bald-faced lie
is an assertion, in this situation, it is impossible for Arangio to assert a proposition she
believes is true. This result is surely counterintuitive: the issue of
whether it is possible for me to sincerely assert something to
you should depend on me (i.e., on whether I can utter the proposition,
etc.), not on you (i.e., on whether you will believe me or not).
Therefore, we should think that a consistent application of the
deceptionist argument misclassifies some sincere assertions.
Given the arguments from steps 1–3, this particular argument cannot
be used as a reason to say that bald-faced lies are not genuine
assertions. In particular, the line of reasoning is such that it
misclassifies some sincere assertions, because the argument begs the
question, generates an unfalsifiable position, and is difficult to
generalise to all bald-faced lies, we can safely assume that it is not a
reason to think that bald-faced lies are not genuine assertions.
However, my argument needs to resolve one more issue: we need to see
whether Artie asserted the proposition he uttered (\(\neg p\)) or the proposition he intended
his hearers to infer (\(p\)). For, if
he asserted the latter, then he asserted what he believed was true and
thus did not lie. I discuss this interpretation below.
Indirect Assertion
The sentence “He’s (She’s) a friend of Dorothy” in the early
20th century US and British homosexual subculture made a
claim about a person who was a homosexual.
Because expressing their sexual orientation was a criminal offence,
homosexuals had to hide it. This sentence made it possible for people to
say that a certain person is gay without uttering that proposition. With
that in mind, consider this situation.
Dorothy. Will and Grace, both familiar with the
terminology of US and British homosexual sub-culture, are at a party
where they meet Grace’s friend Bill. Grace notices that Will fancies
Bill. Thus, when Bill goes to order a drink, Grace says to Will: “Bill’s
a friend of Dorothy, you know. Why don’t you buy him that drink?”
Arguably, Grace asserts that Bill is gay because she means “Bill is
gay” when she utters “Bill’s a friend of Dorothy” and because they are
in a context in which it is common ground that she asserts the
proposition she means (this is what she says) rather than the
proposition she utters (the literal meaning of the uttered sentence).
Our intuitions seem to correspond with this interpretation: it is
natural to think that Will will think that Grace lied to him if Bill
turns out not to be gay but not if it turns out that Bill does not know
a girl named Dorothy.
Dorothy highlights a difficulty that may
arise concerning my cases: in these cases, someone is intending to
communicate proposition \(p\) by means
of uttering \(\neg p\) under certain
circumstances, and hence it may be that they are asserting \(p\), rather than \(\neg p\). That is, it may be that Artie
actually asserts that Tony committed the crime (\(p\)) by uttering “Tony definitely did
not commit the crime” (\(\neg
p\)). The means by which Artie asserts \(p\) (i.e., by uttering \(\neg p\)) is unusual, but it is hardly
impossible to assert one proposition by uttering another.
Indirect assertion is not an uncontroversial concept (see, e.g., LePore
and Stone 2014; Garcı́a-Carpintero 2018) but this interpretation
of Witnessio is plausible and interesting
enough to be seriously considered. I assume that the relevant analysis
of my cases would go something like this. Just as Grace intends that her
utterance “He’s a friend of Dorothy,” in the light of the relevant
subculture’s linguistic conventions, means “Bill is gay,” Artie intends
that his utterance “Tony did not commit the crime,” in the
light of his blushing, be understood as meaning “Tony committed the
crime.” And, because he asserts what he says (standard context) and he
says what he means rather than what he utters, Artie is not lying—since
he believes that the meant proposition is true.
It is pertinent to note that this interpretation is not consistent
with the main idea behind the Pinartio-style
examples. Artie believes that his blushing signals that Artie
believes the opposite of what he says (i.e., it signals that
Artie lies). He does not believe that blushing signals that he
means the opposite of the literal meaning of his utterance. However, this is not a reason not
to consider this interpretation, my descriptions of the cases could be
misguided. Let us therefore consider how the received analyses of
assertion explain Artie’s and Grace’s behaviour.
Artie warrants the truth of the uttered proposition (the
literal meaning of the uttered declarative sentence) rather than the
truth of the proposition he intends the audience to infer from his
behaviour. He proposes that the uttered proposition be added to official
common ground, he represents himself as believing or knowing the uttered
proposition (“Tony is not the murderer”), he commits himself both to the
truth of this proposition and to act in accordance with this
proposition. This is in clear contrast with Grace’s behaviour. Grace
warrants the truth of the “Bill is gay” proposition, she proposes that
“Bill is gay” be added to official common ground, she represents herself
as believing that Bill is gay, she commits herself both to the truth of
this proposition and to acting in accordance with this proposition.
Therefore, the fact that it does not seem odd to think that Grace
indirectly asserts “Bill is gay” is not a reason to think that Artie
indirectly asserts “Tony is the murderer.”
We see that neither Pinocchio nor Artie is willing to accept any
assertoric responsibility for the communicated propositions but only for
the literal meaning of the uttered declarative sentences. Grace,
however, does seem to be taking assertoric responsibility for the “Bill
is gay” proposition. Therefore, while the idea that Artie indirectly
asserts the proposition he intends the police to infer from his blushing
and the uttered proposition is rather interesting, it does not seem to
capture the relevant cases in the right way. Artie and Pinocchio intend
to cause their hearers to realise that they are non-deceptively lying to
them. This is vital for the success of their plan: the hearers should
infer the truth from the fact that the blushing and the nose growing
show that Artie and Pinocchio are lying.
Concluding Remarks
The idea that some lies can be intended to communicate the truth by
having the hearer recognize that the speaker is lying is both plausible
and important. By showing that one can lie without intending to deceive
anyone, tell-tale sign bald-faced lies also vindicate the
non-deceptionist interpretation of the common knowledge bald-faced lies.
Since we now know that lying without intending to deceive is possible,
we can think that common-knowledge bald-faced liars—the gambler, for
instance—could be genuine liars who did not intend to deceive. The
tell-tale kind of bald-faced lies, thus, takes the debate out of the
impasse and suggests that the deceptionist analysis of lying should be
abandoned.
We can now move on and focus on other aspects of lying. For example,
we can start analysing scenarios in which people typically lie to
themselves and try to identify their motivation for such behaviour.
Lying to myself is an intrapersonal analogue of
interpersonal tell-tale sign bald-faced lies: I will
immediately know when I form the intention to lie to myself, I will know
that I will know this, etc. Therefore, tell-tale sign bald-faced lies
can help us to understand a much bigger class of human behaviour.
Because a bald-faced self-liar will probably have similar motives as a
bald-faced interpersonal liar, understanding other people’s
behaviour—namely, why others bald-faced lie to us—will help us to
understand our own behaviour. And vice versa, we will be able
to understand why other people lie better if we investigate our own
motives for lying to ourselves. So, I suggest that this is the direction
in which our analysis of lying should take.