We naturally think that the way things are arranged in space and time is a fundamental feature of the world. In this paper, however, I explore an attractive account of space and time on which this is false. According to what I will call spacetime functionalism, the spatiotemporal structure of the world is not fundamental but instead grounded in the role spacetime regions play in the laws of nature.
This is a radical claim, for the vast majority of philosophers at least implicitly accept what I will call spacetime primitivism, the claim that there are fundamental facts about the spatial and temporal arrangement of the world.1 There are various contemporary scientific hypotheses on which space and time are not fundamental; this paper instead explores the philosophical case for denying spacetime primitivism.2
This paper presents three arguments in favor of the spacetime functionalism. First, I will argue that we don’t need fundamental facts about space and time to make sense of the world—spacetime primitivism is committed to explanatorily redundant facts. Second, spacetime primitivism requires us give up a highly plausible minimality constraint on the fundamental. And third, spacetime primtivism is explanatorily impoverished, as the spacetime functionalist has an elegant explanation for why spatial and temporal relations behave the way they do—for example, why they obey constraints like the triangle inequality, whereas the spacetime primitivist must stipulate objectionably brute necessary connections among the fundamental properties and relations.
Here’s the plan for the paper. section 1 describes the issue at stake between spacetime functionalism and spacetime primitivism. section 2 addresses what I take to be the most serious objection to spacetime functionalism. Then section 3, section 4 and section 5 present the arguments in favor of spacetime primitivism from explanatory redundancy, from metaphysical redundancy, and from the explanatory superiority.
1 Spacetime Primitivism and Spacetime Functionalism
It is a familiar fact that how strongly things interact depends on how far apart they are. For example, whereas a nuclear explosion on the moon would leave me relatively unscathed, a nuclear explosion in my coffee mug would really ruin my day. According to spacetime functionalism, facts like these are constitutive of distance in space and time; it is in virtue of the fact that an explosion in my coffee mug would harm me, but one on the moon wouldn’t, that I’m closer to my coffee mug than to the moon. In slogan form: distance is as distance does. On this view, the spatiotemporal structure of the world is not fundamental but is instead grounded in its nomic structure. The spacetime primitivist, on the other hand, holds that there are fundamental facts about how things are arranged in space and time—whether those facts concern distance relations among objects or the structure of substantival spacetime.
On the version of spacetime functionalism I will develop here, spacetime regions are fundamental, but their geometrical structure is derivative. Instead, there are fundamental facts about how regions of spacetime are disposed to interact, and the geometry of the world emerges from this basis. That is, there are no fundamental spatiotemporal relations among regions; in their place there are fundamental facts about physically necessary conditionals linking individual regions, of the form: it is physically necessary that if region \(r_1\) has qualitative profile \(p_1\), then region \(r_2\) has qualitative profile \(p_2\). As I will explain below, this is enough to capture the spatiotemporal structure of the world in its entirety.
The question at stake between the spacetime primitivist and the spacetime functionalist is independent of another debate about the metaphysics of spacetime: that between substantivalism and relationism.
Substantivalists hold that regions of spacetime exist independently of material objects.3 Relationists, on the other hand, hold that claims about regions of spacetime are grounded in the spatiotemporal relations among material objects.
This is a dispute about which entities instantiate the fundamental spatiotemporal properties and relations: material objects, or spacetime regions?4
The issue I tackle in this paper is independent of substantivalism-relationalism debate, since it concerns the spatiotemporal relations themselves, not their relata. Spacetime primitivism is the claim that some spatiotemporal properties or relations are fundamental. A spacetime primitivist may be relationist (for example, by holding that there are fundamental distance relations among material objects) or a substantivalist (by holding that spacetime regions instantiate fundamental relations like being two meters from or properties like having a length of two meters.)5
The spacetime functionalist denies that there are any fundamental spatiotemporal properties or relations. Instead, the spatial and temporal distance between things is grounded facts about how they interact.
For the purpose of the paper I will assume that substantivalism is true, so that (some) regions of spacetime (or its parts) are fundamental entities.6 A substantivalist spacetime functionalist holds that while spacetime points and regions are fundamental entities they do not instantiate any fundamental spatiotemporal properties. Instead, the spatial and temporal distance between two points is determined by how they interact; that is, how the properties instantiated at one location affects which properties are instantiated at the other location.7
One might object that it makes no sense to claim that there are spacetime regions that have no fundamental spatiotemporal structure. But this is not so, given that substantivalism and primitivism are independent. The central commitment of substantivalism is that there is an object—the spacetime manifold—which plays a distinctive metaphysical role. A central part of this role is that material objects are either located at (or, for the supersubstantivalist, identical to) parts of the spacetime manifold. If primitivism is correct then the structure of the spacetime manifold is determined by the distribution of the fundamental spatiotemporal properties or relations. The view I am proposing is that the spacetime manifold is fundamental, but has its structure determined by the functional roles of its parts, where these functional roles are explained in terms of physically necessity.8
Because the spacetime functionalist explains the world’s spatiotemporal structure in terms of physical necessity, the spacetime functionalist cannot be a Humean reductionist. The Humean reductionist about laws of nature holds that the laws are grounded in the spatiotemporal distribution of the fundamental properties.9 Since facts about the distribution of properties are determined by the structure of space and time, the Humean must be a spacetime primitivist. The spacetime functionalist reverses the direction of explanation: the world’s spatiotemporal structure is grounded in nomic facts.
The spacetime functionalist must therefore be a non-Humean. To be a non-Humean is to hold that a complete description of fundamental reality must mention facts about laws, causation, dispositions, or some related nomic notion.10 While spacetime functionalism is compatible with any of the mainstream non-Humean accounts of laws, I will assume a fairly minimalist non-Humean account according to which it is a fundamental feature of the world that certain propositions are physically necessary. I will express these propositions in terms of a primitive sentence operator, “\(L...\)”, to be read as “it is physically necessary that …”.
It is worth noting that the Humean and the spacetime functionalist both take something to be fundamental that the other regards as derivative. One of the upshots of this paper is that many of the Humean arguments against primitivism about laws—for example, that non-Humean facts are unnecessary, epistemically unreachable, or that there is no explanation of how they do the work they were posited to do—militate equally against the Humean commitment to spacetime primitivism.
If spacetime primitivism is correct then the world’s spatiotemporal structure is independent of its causal structure, so that it is in principle possible for things to be arranged differently in space and time although they interact just like they actually do.
For example, consider a scenario that is just like the world, but in which everything is much smaller. Suppose the Earth were the size of a beach ball. The moon would be the size of a softball, orbiting 40 feet away. The sun, four school-bus-lengths across, would be three miles away. A tiny version of you, about the size a virus, is reading an even tinier paper.
Or instead, imagine a scenario, again just like the actual world, but in which everything is much larger than it actually is. Suppose protons were the size of beach balls. Hydrogen atoms would be about 5 miles across. You are a colossal giant, spanning the actual distance from the Earth to the Sun.
In order for these to be worlds in which things causally interact just like they actually do, the laws must be different: if insects were the size of cars and governed by our laws they would collapse under their own weight. But we can imagine larger insects that are not made of any more molecules than they actually are, governed by laws that result in them engaging in precisely the same behavior as in the actual world.
In the smaller and larger worlds described above, distance ratios are unchanged: the size of the earth relative to the sun is the same. The spacetime primitivist could hold that the fundamental distance facts concern distance ratios, and conclude that these these are merely a rediscriptions of the actual world.11
But if facts about distance are independent of facts about causal interaction then we can consider more radical worlds in which things interact just as they actually do but in which distance ratios are not preserved. Consider, for example, a world in which things shrink (or grow) over time, but in which the laws also change to compensate, so that things behave just like they actually do.12
We can also consider worlds with different temporal structure. Suppose the world were “sped up” but otherwise unchanged, so that exactly the same events occur as in the actual world, but the time separating corresponding events is half as long as it actually is. Or consider a “slowing down” world, so that the same causal processes occur but at slower and slower rates.
If spacetime structure is truly independent of the world’s causal structure then we can describe scenarios with the same causal facts in which even the world’s topological structure is different. Suppose that I am actually a few meters from you, trying to persuade you of the truth pf spacetime functionalism. Now consider a world in which things causally interact just as they actually do but in which I am many light-years away. The region a few meters away, in which I appear to be located, in fact contains a nuclear explosion. But, happily, the region that contains the explosion interacts with other regions as if it had the location of the region that contains me, many light-years away, so you are unharmed. And conversely, the region I am in has the functional role of a region that it only a few meters from you. So, photons leaving my skin reach your retina, and the air vibrations caused by vocal chords cause the air inside your ear to vibrate too. More generally, even though this world has a drastically different spatiotemporal arrangement, things causally interact just like they actually do.13
These worlds disagree about how far apart things are in space and time. But they do not disagree about what causes what; in each world, smoking causes cancer, Hitler’s invasion of Poland causes WWII, and Muhammad Ali delivers a knockout blow to George Foreman.14 Of course, since these worlds have different spatial and temporal arrangements there is a clear sense in which things don’t causally interact in the way they actually do. After all, although in each world I can cause there to be a fresh mug of coffee on my desk, the worlds disagree over the size of the mug of coffee that would result. But there is an equally intuitive sense in which they agree about what causes what.
This is because these worlds have something important in common concerning the roles space and time play in the laws. For example, each world contains a region that contains something that looks and behaves like my coffee mug. I will say that each world contains a region that plays the same functional role as the region that contains my coffee mug. More generally, there is a mapping between these worlds that maps regions to regions with the same functional role. I’ll say these worlds have the same causal structure. (Remember, however, that it is not causation but facts about physical necessity that are fundamental on the version of spacetime functionalism I will develop here.)
Since the spacetime functionalist claims that geometrical structure of the world is grounded in how things interact, if spacetime functionalism is correct these scenarios do not, after all, correspond to different possibilities: since the worlds have the same causal structure they therefore have the same spatiotemporal structure.
Is this a count in favor of spacetime functionalism, because these scenarios involve making distinctions without differences? Or does this count against the theory since it fails to recognize distinct possibilities? I’m not sure; I find my intuitions to pull in both directions. So one response is to say with David Armstrong, spoils to the victor! and conclude that we should let our intuitions be guided by theory, not vice versa. But I am happy to grant that this is the source of some weak intuitive pressure against spacetime functionalism. Intuitions about the nature of fundamental reality must sometimes be revised in the face of countervailing evidence, as with the appearance that the sun revolves around the Earth, or that some events are objectively simultaneous. Similarly, I will argue that the evidence from intuitions against spacetime functionalism is outweighed by the arguments in favor of the view.
I’ll now explicate the notion of causal structure I have in mind by explaining what it takes for two worlds to have the same causal structure. What is shared across the radically different worlds I have described? Intuitively, one thing worlds with the same causal structure agree on is there is an object that looks and behaves like Barack Obama. But we can’t capture this with the claim that the worlds all contain a duplicate of Obama, since duplication is standardly defined so that two objects are duplicates only if their parts stand in the same spatial relations.15
Let us use a slightly different notion instead. Say that a property or relation is qualitative iff it is non-spatiotemporal. Two objects are qualitative duplicates when they share all qualitative intrinsic properties and relations.16 Objects can be qualitative duplicates even though they are not duplicates; something may be a qualitative duplicate of Obama even though it’s millions of times larger. Qualitative duplicates have the same qualitative profile, where the qualitative profile of an object is determined by the intrinsic qualitative properties and relations instantiated by its parts.
Armed with the notion of qualitative duplication, we can express one thing that is shared between worlds with the same causal structure: if two worlds \(w_1\) and \(w_2\) have the same causal structure then there is a one-one mapping between regions in the worlds that maps every region to a qualitative duplicate region.
But the worlds agree on more than this; they also agree about how things interact. In each world, for example, a nuclear explosion in my coffee mug would harm my dog.
The functional role of a region is determined by how it interacts with other regions; this in turn is determined by the physically necessary conditionals linking the pattern of properties in that region to the properties of other regions. For example, suppose that at time \(t\) the world is just like it actually is except that a nuclear explosion has just detonated inside my coffee mug. Let \(r_{t}\) be the time-slice of the world at \(t\), and \(r_t\*\) be an instantaneous region a few moments later.17 Let \(\phi\) be a complete intrinsic description of \(r_{t}\), and let \(\psi\) be a complete intrinsic description of \(r_t\*\). Then if the laws are deterministic, the following physically necessary conditional will hold:
(1) \(L(\phi(r_{t}) \rightarrow \psi(r_{t\*})).\)
(If the laws are chancy, then there will be physically necessary conditional whose consequent specifies the probability that \(r_t\*\) is \(\psi\).)
However, because a region’s functional role should not encode facts about its spatiotemporal structure, it should be characterized in terms of qualitative physically necessary conditionals. Let \(\phi_q\) and \(psi_q\) be specifications of the qualitative profile of \(r_{t}\) and \(r_t\*\). If (1) is true then so is:
(1\(_q\)) \(L(\phi_q(r_{t}) \rightarrow \psi_q(r_{t\*}))\)
I will say that qualitative conditionals like (1\(_q\)) describe relations of lawful dependence between regions. Since qualitative conditionals like (1\(_q\)) do not presuppose facts about the spatiotemporal arrangement of things in \(r_{t}\) and \(r_t\*\), they offer a way to capture what functionally equivalent worlds have in common.18
Not all regions are alike; space and time are different. The laws of nature describe how the world evolves over time, not how it evolves from left to right. That is, a specification of what the world is like at a given time, together with the laws, provides a lot of information about what the world is like at other times.19 But the laws together with a specification of what the world is like in a spatial region on its own tells us nothing about what the world is like outside that region.20
Because of the special role that time plays in the laws, I’ll begin by saying what it takes for two regions that are time-slices to have the same functional role. Intuitively, two time-slices have the same functional role if and only if they exert similar influences on and are influenced similarly by other regions. That is, if two time-slices have the same functional role then they have same forward-directed and the same backward-directed functional role. The forward-directed functional role of a region concerns what is entailed by the laws together with a description of that region. The backward-directed functional role of a region instead concerns what, together with the laws, entail that that region has various properties. (Here, “forward” and “backwards” mean nomically forward or backward, where this can be directly defined in terms of the laws; I am not assuming any connection to the direction of time).
Two time slices have the same forward directed functional role if they have qualitatively identical effects whenever they are qualitatively identical. Recall that two regions \(r_1\) and \(r_2\) are qualitatively identical if and only if there is a mapping \(M\) between points of \(r_1\) and \(r_2\) such that for any point \(p\) of \(r_1\) and any property \(\phi\), \(\phi(p)\) if and only if \(\phi(M(p))\). Let us write the claim that two regions \(r_1\), \(r_2\) are qualitatively identical as \(r_1 \approx r_2\).
Then we can say what it takes for two time-slices to have the same forward-looking functional role in the following way:
Functional Role\(_{timeslice(f)}\). Two time-slices \(r_1\), \(r_2\) have same forward-looking functional role if for any region \(r_3\) and any qualitative profiles \(q_1\) and \(q_2\), if \(L(q_1(r_1) \rightarrow q_2(r_3))\) then there is some region \(r_4\) such that \(L(r_1 \approx r_2 \rightarrow r_3 \approx r_4.)\)21
Intuitively, this captures the fact that if detonating a nuclear bomb in my coffee mug would produce an explosion in my apartment, then for any timeslice with the same functional role, a detonation in my coffee mug would product a explosion in my apartment as well.
Backward-looking functional roles can be characterized in a similar way:
Functional Role\(_{timeslice(b)}\). Two time-slices \(r_1\) and \(r_2\) have same backward-looking functional role if for any region \(r_3\) and any qualitative profiles \(q_1\) and \(q_2\), if \(L(q_1(r_3) \rightarrow q_2(r_2))\) then there is some region \(r_4\) such that \(L(r_4 \approx r_3 \rightarrow r_1 \approx r_2.)\)
When two regions are qualitatively identical, there may be more than one qualitative-property-preserving between their points, as in the case, for example, when both regions have two qualitatively identical subregions. Two regions play the same functional role only if there exists a mapping on which they have the same forward-looking and backward-looking functional role, and so it is important to keep track of which mapping is being appealed to; let \(r_1 \approx_M r_2\) mean that \(M\) is a qualitative-property-preserving mapping between \(r_1\) and \(r_2\).
Two regions have the same functional role if and only if there is a mapping \(M\) that satisfies the consequent of both Functional Role\(_{ts(b)}\) and Functional Role\(_{ts(f)}\).22 Call such a mapping an entailment-preserving mapping; two regions have the same functional role if there is an entailment-preserving mapping between them.
One might worry that since the only physically necessary conditionals linking regions are those that concern time-slices, they don’t give us the resources to capture the functional role of spatial regions. But the functional role of a spatial region can be characterized in terms of the functional role of the time-slice that contains it. For example, consider the spatial region that at time \(t\) contains my coffee mug, \(r_{mug}\). Intuitively, the laws tell us something about the effects the qualitative profile of \(r_{mug}\) has on other regions, even if specifying the qualitative profile of \(r_{mug}\) alone entails nothing specific about other regions. We can cash this out by appeal to the conditional entailments associated with \(r_{mug}\). In general:
Functional Role\((spatial)\). Two spatial regions \(r_1\) and \(r_2\) have the same functional role if and only if there are time-slices \(ts_1\) and \(ts_2\) such that (a) \(r_1\) is part of \(ts_1\), \(r_2\) is part of \(ts_2\), and \(ts_1\) and \(ts2_1\) have the same functional role, and (b) any entailment-preserving mapping M between \(ts_1\) and \(ts_2\) maps \(r_1\) to \(r_2\).
We now have the resources to say what it takes for worlds to have the same causal structure:
Causal Structure. Two worlds \(w_1\), \(w_2\) have the same causal structure if and only if there is a one-one mapping \(M\) between regions of \(w_1\) and regions of \(w_2\) that maps every region to a region with the same functional role.
This captures what is shared between the worlds we looked at above: in each scenario, for every region in the actual world we can find a region that plays the same functional role.23
The spacetime functionalist makes three distinctive claims. Two concern the nature of fundamental reality:
Anti-Primitivism. There are no fundamental spatiotemporal properties or relations.
Anti-Humeanism. There are fundamental facts about physical necessity.
The spacetime functionalist is not a spatial nihilist; rather, she holds an explanatory thesis about how facts about spacetime structure emerge from what is fundamental:
Functionalism. The spatiotemporal arrangement of the world is grounded in its causal structure.
On this view, when God created the world He made the spacetime regions and determined the facts about physical necessity, and the structure of space and time emerged from this basis. Spacetime regions are fundamental, but their geometric structure is derivative.
I have not given a formula for calculating what spatiotemporal facts would emerge given arbitrary specifications of the world’s causal structure. But a grounding claim can be substantive and interesting in the absence of such a formula: one can surely hold that phenomenal states are grounded in brain states without having to hand a formula that predicts which phenomenal states emerge under various brain states. Nevertheless, we can identify a substantive constraint governing the emergence of spacetime structure:
Supervenient Spacetime. If there is a mapping \(M\) between regions in \(w_1\) and \(w_2\) that maps every region to a region that plays the same functional role, then \(M\) also maps regions to regions with the same spatiotemporal features.
Before moving on to argue for spacetime primitivism, I will first make clear that while the claim that spacetime is derivative or “emergent” is not new, spacetime functionalism differs in important ways from the theses that are typically discussed in the literature under this label.24
Some theories that hold that spacetime is emergent are much weaker than spacetime functionalism, since they hold that there is some kind of fundamental spatial or geometric structure, although the structure of familiar three-dimensional space and time are derivative.25 I will treat these claims as versions of spacetime primitivism, since they posit fundamental spatial structure.
Other theories that hold spacetime is emergent are much stronger than spacetime functionalism, since they endorse novel physical theories governing the behavior of the fundamental ontology.26 I will set these theories aside, since I want to focus on the philosophical rather than the physical arguments for denying spacetime primitivism.
One class of theories in particular that received a lot of attention with the advent of special relativity are causal theories of time or spacetime such as those developed by Reichenbach (1958), Grünbaum (1963), Winnie (1977) and van Fraassen (1970).27 What these theories have in common is that they aim to recapture the geometry of spacetime from facts about a primitive notion of causal connectability among points, where to say two events are causally connectable means something like: it is physically possible for a signal (i.e. a massive particle or a light pulse) to be sent from one to the other. This program is confronted by various technical problems. van Fraassen (1972) But crucially, the failure of causal theories of spacetime would not undermine spacetime functionalism because the reduction base of these theories is much sparser than that of spacetime functionalism. This is because there are many facts about physical necessity (for example, the fact that it is physically necessary that a world otherwise like this one but with a nuclear explosion in my coffee mug is one in which I die) that are not settled by the facts about causal connectability.
2 Is Spacetime Functionalism too Complicated?
A distinctive feature of the spacetime primitivist’s account of fundamental reality is that the physically necessary conditionals linking regions are fundamental. This is opposed to a standard approach to laws and spacetime according to which these conditionals are derivative: on this standard view, God settled the arrangement of things in spacetime, and then settled the laws, and it is in virtue of these facts that it is physically necessary that if my coffee contains a nuclear explosion (and the world is otherwise unaltered) then I will die. The spacetime functionalist instead reverses the order of explanation by holding that physically necessary conditionals linking particular regions are fundamental.
This is an unfamiliar way of thinking about the fundamental nomic structure of the world. But are there good reasons to resist it?
One objection is that the spacetime functionalist’s theory is too complex, for she must appeal to physical necessary conditionals linking incredibly many different individual regions.
The bare concern about complexity seems misplaced, however. After all, according to spacetime primitivists, it is a brute fact that some points but not others are close together; the spacetime functionalist merely replaces these individualistic facts with facts about direct dependence.
Perhaps a better way to make this objection is to appeal to the fact that complexity in the laws is much worse than complexity in contingent facts, and complain that the laws of the spacetime functionalist are incredibly complicated. In response, note that there is a clear sense in which there is much less structure in the fundamental facts about physical necessity according to the spacetime functionalist than there is for the spacetime primitivist! This is because the spacetime primitivist believes that the laws encode facts about spacetime structure: worlds with the same causal structure in general have different laws by the lights of the spacetime primitivist. The spacetime functionalist, on other hand, denies that the laws have enough structure to distinguish between these worlds.
A different way of developing this objection is to complain that the spacetime functionalist’s fundamental nomic facts, which concern physically necessary conditionals linking individual regions, cannot be stated simply. The spacetime primitivist, on the other hand, can state her fundamental nomic facts (if she holds that there are any!) by appeal to a small number of general laws.
In response, the spacetime functionalist can grant that the laws of nature are precisely those laws found in physics journals. It’s just that the laws, which are stated in terms of spatiotemporal structure, are not stated in fundamental terms. The familiar laws of nature that are stated in terms of spatiotemporal structure merely serve as simple and elegant ways of encoding the fundamental facts about physical necessity. In other words, the spacetime functionalist can hold that the standard laws are scientifically fundamental, while facts about physical possibility are metaphysically fundamental.
We should distinguish between scientific explanation and metaphysical explanation. For example, while the fact that a certain atom is ionized at \(t_2\) might be scientifically explained by the fact that it absorbed some radiation at \(t_1\). But the fact that it absorbed some radiation is not what makes it true that it is ionized. It is ionized in virtue of having a different number of protons and electrons.
Humeans about laws appeal to this distinction in response to the charge that their account of laws is circular. Humeans claim that the fact that some regularity \(R\) is a law obtains at least partially in virtue of the fact that \(R\) is a regularity. But laws are supposed to explain their instances. So that \(R\) is a law is explained by \(R\) (from Humeanism) and \(R\) is explained by the fact that \(R\) is a law (from the explanatoriness of laws). Armstrong (1983) claims that this makes the account circular. Humeans (like Loewer 2012) may respond by pointing out that the senses of explanation at issue are different. Laws are metaphysically explained by their instances, but instances are scientifically explained by the laws.28
The spacetime functionalist can make a similar move; she can claim that the familiar laws that are framed in terms of spacetime are scientifically fundamental, while facts about physical necessity are nonetheless metaphysically fundamental.
There are independent, quite general reasons to think that the scientifically fundamental laws are not metaphysically fundamental—that is, not state in metaphysically fundamental terms.29
The fundamental physical laws are stated using defined notions. But defined notions are plausibly fundamental—they are less fundamental than the notions they are defined in terms of. For example, the fundamental scientific laws are differential equations; they say how the rate of change of one quantity relates to other quantities. But facts about rates of change, like acceleration, are not metaphysically fundamental. The acceleration of some body at time \(t\) is defined as the limit of the rate of change of velocity in successively smaller time periods containing \(t\). Velocity is similarly defined in terms of position. But scientists feel no need to state laws about rates of change as very complicated claims about limits, and if they did the laws would become dramatically less simple.30
Another reason for thinking that the scientifically fundamental laws are not metaphysically fundamental is that scientific laws are mathematical claims. A very plausible explanation of this fact is that even though the world does not have fundamental mathematical structure itself—a two meter rod doesn’t stand in the same relation to a three meter rod as the number 2 stands in to the number 3—we may usefully use mathematical structures to represent physical structures. But there are obvious reasons for physicists to describe the world mathematically even if the world has no fundamental mathematical structure: precisely because it is simpler and more elegant and easier to reason about the mathematical description.
The lesson, it seems, is that scientists deliberately state the laws in non-fundamental terms for the sake of the simplicity gained.
Of course this is perfectly compatible with there being a close connection between the scientifically fundamental and metaphysically fundamental laws, so that the fact that some property appears in the scientifically fundamental laws is defeasible evidence that it is metaphysically fundamental. But there are already independent compelling reasons to think that the metaphysically fundamental laws are too complicated to be considered candidates for being scientific laws. So it is no objection to the spacetime functionalist that her view has this feature as well.
Perhaps what is really driving the objection is that the spacetime functionalist posits a vast number of independent fundamental nomic facts, whereas the spacetime primitivist can get by with positing only a small number of fundamental laws. This, we might think, is a serious cost for spacetime functionalism.
Simplicity is relevant to theory choice in a few different ways. Theories that attribute less structure (nomic or non-nomic) to the world are preferable. Since spacetime functionalism attributes less structure to the world than spacetime primitivism, this is not what drives this objection. A different principle concerning simplicity is that theories that can be stated simply and elegantly are better theories. Again, this principle does not count against spacetime functionalism because there is a perfectly simple way of stating the theory in terms of the scientifically fundamental laws. The principle that is required to drive the objection under discussion must be something like:
Nomic Sparseness (NS). All else equal, we should prefer a theory on which there are there are a small number of fundamental nomic facts.
If (NS) is a constraint on theory choice then this gives us some reason to resist spacetime functionalism. (Although I will also argue that all else is not equal.) However, it is unclear what the motivation for (NS) would be. The motivation does not come from an Occamist preference for theories that attribute less structure to the world. Nor does it come from a preference for theories that can be stated simply. Moreover, if (NS) were correct then it would count against much more than just spacetime primitivism. For example, according to dispositional essentialism, the fundamental nomic facts concern the essences of the fundamental properties. If there are uncountably many determinate mass properties, as many suppose, then the dispositional essentialist holds that there are a vast number of fundamental nomic facts. But however the merits of dispositional essentialism compare to other non-Humean accounts, it is odd to think—and no one has yet claimed—that this feature of the view makes the theory worse. This suggests that (NS) should not play a significant role in theory choice.
The mere fact that the scientifically fundamental laws are not metaphysically fundamental is not particular to spacetime functionalism. Moreover, there are independent reasons to think the laws, when stated in metaphysically fundamental terms, will be vastly more complicated than their canonical statements. Since the nomic facts that the spacetime functionalist recognizes are logically weaker than those posited by the spacetime primitivist (because they distinguish between fewer possibilities), the complaint that spacetime functionalism is overly complicated is mistaken. And the mere fact that the spacetime functionalist must recognize many independent fundamental facts about physical necessity is no reason to object to the view. So I conclude that none of the objections to positing fundamental facts about physical necessity are very compelling.
3 The Argument from Metaphysical Redundancy
David Lewis said of the perfectly natural properties and relations that “there are only just enough of them to characterize things completely and without redundancy” (Lewis 1986a, 60).31 There is something very intuitive about this thought. When God created the world, we might imagine, he didn’t do unnecessary work. The fundamental facts should plausibly form a minimal supervenience base, so that everything supervenes on the fundamental facts but not on any proper subset of them. If the fundamental facts failed to form a minimal supervenience base, then some of them wouldn’t be needed to characterize the world. I’ll say facts like this are metaphysically redundant.
According to the spacetime primitivist, spatiotemporal properties and relations are fundamental. But as I will argue, facts about them do not form a mimimal supervenience base. So there must be metaphysical redundancy in the spatiotemoral primivist’s account of the world. This is a count against spacetime primitivism.
I’ll first explain why this is the case for the most naïve version of spacetime primitivism, and then explain why any more sophisticated version fails to deliver a minimal supervenience base as well.
Consider a spacetime primitivist who regiments the structure of spacetime by positing a family of external relations, the distance relations.32 That is, the relations one meter apart, two meters apart, seventeen meters apart and so on are all fundamental.
On this view, in order for God to determine how things are arranged in space at a given time He must decide separately, for every material object, which distance relations it stands in. Suppose He starts with my fridge; it is two feet from my coffee maker, 200 miles from Obama, 4000 miles from Putin, and so on.33 Next, He determines all the distances the Eiffel Tower stands in: it is 95,000 miles from the South Pole, 239,000 miles from the moon, and so on. Third and fourth, He determines for each object its distance from the center of the sun and its distance from the summit of mount Everest. If this way of thinking about distance is correct, God has not even completed a tiny fraction of the work he needs to do to settle the distance facts once he has settled which distances these four objects stand in. But any additional work he does is unnecessary, for the distance relations these four objects stand in is enough to determine the distance between any arbitrary objects in the universe.
Say we want to know how far apart Obama and Putin are. According to the spacetime primitivist this is to ask which fundamental distance relation holds between them. But how far apart they are is already determined by the relations we have specified! For if we know how far Obama and Putin are from my fridge, the Eiffel Tower, mount Everest and the Sun, then by trilateration we know how far apart they are.34 So this fact about the distance between Obama and Putin is metaphysically redundant. The spacetime primitivist could claim that only some facts about distances are fundamental. But any choice of some distance relations over others will be implausibly arbitrary.
Rather than taking distance relations as fundamental, the spacetime primitivist could instead encode facts about distance in other terms. But however she regiments the structure of spacetime her account will entail that there are metaphysically redundandant fundamental facts.
For example, she could posit two fundamental relations, betweenness and congruence.35 Congruence holds between four points \(p_1,p_2,p_3,p_4\) just in case the distance between \(p_1\) and \(p_2\) is the same as the distance between \(p_3\) and \(p_4\). But this account suffers from the same problem: if my coffee mug and my toaster bear congruence to your coffee mug and toaster and also to Fred’s coffee mug and toaster, then this entails that your and Fred’s mugs and toasters stand in congruence too. So this last fact is redundant.
The primitivist could instead take facts about path lengths to be basic. The distance between two points can then be defined as the length of the shortest path between them.36 This avoids the redundancy that arose with distance relations, since the length of the shortest path between Obama and Putin is not settled by the lengths of the paths between my fridge, the Eiffel tower and the Sun and everything else. But taking path lengths to be fundamental results in redundancy of another form. Let a path be a fusion of points, and suppose we assign each path a positive real number that represents its length in meters.37 Since we are assuming that space is dense, every path \(p\) is composed of two subpaths \(p_1\) and \(p_2\). The length of a path is determined by the length of all the subpaths that compose it. So if the length of \(p_1\) and \(p_2\) is determined, there is no need to then go on to determine the length of \(p\). So any fundamental fact about the length of \(p\) would be metaphysically redundant. But there was nothing special about \(p\); and therefore every path length fact is metaphysically redundant.
Finally, the primitivist could posit a fundamental geometric property of spacetime points that is aptly described by a mathematical object called a metric tensor. In effect, the metric tensor of a point \(p\) encodes information about distances within an infinitesimal neighborhood of \(p\).38 The length of a path \(p\) can then be obtained by integrating along \(p\).39
But since the metric tensor at \(p\) provides information about the distance structure nearby \(p\), redundancy re-arises. I’ll illustrate this point with another example of a neighborhood-dependent property, velocity. The velocity of some object at time \(t\) is a matter of what the object does nearby \(t\): the velocity of \(o\) at \(t\) is the limit of the average velocity of \(o\) in smaller and smaller intervals of time containing \(t\). This means that specifying the instantaneous velocity of an object at every time involves redundancy. Suppose \(o\) traveles on some smooth trajectory between \(t_1\) and \(t_2\), and that the velocity of \(o\) at every time between \(t_1\) and \(t_2\) is given except for some instant \(t_i\). Because velocity is defined in terms of nearby instants, the velocity of \(o\) at \(t_i\) is already settled by velocities at other times. So specifying the velocity at \(t_i\) would be redundant. But there was nothing special about \(t_i\), and so the same is true of every fact about \(o\)’s velocity.40 The situation with metric tensor facts is precisely analogous. Suppose the metric tensor at every point in some space except for \(p\) is given. Then it is determined exactly what the metric tensor at \(p\) is. So specifying the metric tensor at \(p\) in addition would be redundant.41
This problem does not arise for the spacetime functionalist. This is because xxx
If spacetime primitivism is correct then there is no non-arbitrary, non-redundant supervenience base for the world. This is a reason to prefer spacetime functionalism, for which these problems do not arise since the world’s minimal supervenience base doesn’t include facts about spatial or temporal distance.
4 The Argument from Explanatory Power
The spatiotemporal primitivist holds that spatiotemporal properties and relations are fundamental. This makes it puzzling that spatiotemporal relations march in lockstep. For example, the fact that \(a\) is two meters from \(b\) and \(b\) is two meters from \(c\) imposes constraints on possible distances between \(a\) and \(c\). Some will be willing to go as far as David Hume and insist that the basic building blocks of the world are “entirely loose and separate” (1975, 61). Even for those who doubt the fundamental world is entirely “loose”, however, it hard to deny that a theory is better if it is able to explain constraints among the fundamental properties and relations instead of having to leave them as brute stipulations.
Necessary connections call out for explanation. For example, many philosophers infer from the fact that normative properties supervene on natural properties that normative properties are grounded in natural properties, precisely because this supervenience ought to be explained. If natural and normative properties were both fundamental, the thought goes, it would be mysterious why they were so nicely choreographed. We might imagine that God creates the world, one fundamental property at a time. Once he has settled the distribution of the natural properties, he goes on to specify the distribution of normative properties, but necessarily does so in precisely such a way that one class of properties supervenes on the other. But why? Why should God’s creative powers have to follow this pattern?
One can hold that necessary connections should be explained whenever possible without being committed to the radical Humean doctrine that there are no necessary connections at the fundamental level. Consider David Lewis’ complaint about David Armstrong’s account of laws of nature. On Armstrong’s account it is a law that anything with F has G if and only if F bears the second-order relation nomic necessitation (or \(N\)) to G. Lewis objects that no explanation has been given for why the fact that N(F,G) should entail that anything with F also has G:
Whatever N may be, I cannot see how it could be absolutely impossible to have N(F,G) and Fa without Ga […] The mystery is somewhat hidden by Armstrong’s terminology […] who would be surprised to hear that if F “necessitates” G and a has F, then a must have G? But I say that N deserves the name of “necessitation” only if, somehow, it really can enter into the requisite necessary connections. It can’t enter into them just by bearing a name, any more than one can have mighty biceps just by being called “Armstrong”. (1983, 366)
Lewis seems to think that there is something especially problematic about Armstrong’s theory. I don’t think that’s right. Armstrong posits a special second-order relation to make sense of laws. But it is a virtue, not a vice, of Armstrong’s account that he does not merely posit and stop there. He says something about how his chosen machinery is supposed to behave. The phenomenon Lewis is objecting to is utterly mundane: any theory must have some entities or primitives that aren’t explained in other terms, and any interesting theory will say something about how these primitive features behave.
Lewis is a spacetime primitivist. He recognizes a family of perfectly natural external relations, the distances. But for them to play the role of distances they must obey certain constraints, like the triangle inequality: it had better be the case that for any three points \(a\), \(b\) and \(c\), the distance between \(a\) and \(b\) added to the distance between \(b\) and \(c\) is not more than the distance between \(a\) and \(c\). And it had also better be the case that a given pair of points only ever stand in one of these fundamental external relations: two points cannot stand in multiple distance relations. How does Lewis explain these constraints? He doesn’t. That \(a\) is \(1m\) from \(b\), \(b\) is \(1m\) from \(c\), and \(a\) is \(1m\) from \(c\) are all distinct, basic states of affairs. We might imagine Armstrong offering a parody of Lewis’ complaint:
Whatever these distance relations may be, I cannot see how it could be absolutely impossible to have one-meter(a,b), one-meter(b,c) and twenty-meters(a,c). I say that these relations deserve the name “distances” only if, somehow, they can really obey the necessary constraints. They cannot obey them just by bearing a name, any more than [etc.]
Still, Lewis does have a legitimate complaint against Armstrong. It is that Armstrong posits necessary connections where he doesn’t need to. Armstrong must simply stipulate that nomic necessitation behaves in the way he claims it does. The Humean reductionist about laws need not make any such stipulation.
We can profitably think of Lewis’s complaint as an appeal to a certain kind of parsimony.
Theories that make fewer assumptions are, all else equal, better theories. This principle takes on a few different guises in metaphysics. It’s familiar to distinguish between the ontology of a theory (which things it says exist) and its ideology (those expressions of the theory which are unexplained, the primitives of the theory.) We can distinguish between varieties of simplicity correspondingly. Ontologically simpler theories posit fewer (types or tokens of) entities. Ideologically simpler theories use fewer primitive expressions.
But there is a further notion of simplicity that does not take either of these forms. Say that axiomatically simpler theories are those that contain fewer stipulations about how the primitives of the theory behave.
Suppose the spacetime primitivist accounts for the structure of space and time by positing a family of perfectly natural external relations, the distance relations. These relations must be stipulated to behave in certain ways if they are apt to play the role of distance relations. First, they exclude one another. It had better not be possible for two things to stand in hundreds of different distance relations. And second, they must obey broader constraints in their distribution, like the triangle inequality: it had better be true that for any three objects, \(o_1\),\(o_2\),\(o_3\), the distance between \(o_1\) and \(o_3\) is at most the sum of the distances between \(o_1\) and \(o_2\) and \(o_2\) and \(o_3\).42 This a cost that the spacetime functionalist avoids.
As we saw in the previous chapter a more sophisticated spacetime primitivist need not regard distance relations as fundamental. But however the spacetime primitivist accounts for the structure of space the same problems will reemerge for similar reasons.
For example, suppose that path lengths are fundamental and facts about the distance between two points obtain in virtue of facts about the length of the shortest path between them. Maudlin (2007) claims that the benefit of taking path length to be prior is that constraints like the triangle inequality emerge by definition instead of having to be stipulated. But as we saw in the previous section there are still plenty of constraints on path lengths that must be postulated. For example, we must stipulate that the length of a path is always equal to the sum of the lengths of the subpaths composing it.43
These unexplained stipulations are theoretical costs. We should avoid positing necessary constraints whenever we can; all else equal they make a theory worse. Spacetime primitivists must simply postulate that their favored primitives obey certain constraints such as the triangle inequality. The spacetime functionalist, on the other hand, has no need to, since these constraints naturally emerge from the nomic facts to which spacetime reduces.
The spacetime functionalist theorist takes facts about nomic necessity to be fundamental. We saw that Armstrong must stipulate that nomic-necessitation behaves in a certain way. But there is nothing unique about Armstrong’s account in this respect; any non-Humean must make an analogous claim.44 So the spacetime functionalist should stipulate that \(L(p)\) entails \(p\).
But once this constraint is in place the spacetime functionalist has a ready explanation for the constraints that the primitivist must take for granted. Take the fact that no two points can stand in more than one distance relation. This would require that one point is associated with two different and incompatible sets of physically necessary conditionals. For example, suppose that \(p_1\) and \(p_2\) are both one meter and two meters apart. Then it is physically necessary that if there is a lonely object with mass \(m\) at \(p_1\) then the gravitational field at \(p_2\) will be \(g_1\), and also physically necessary that it be \(g_2\). But this would require the same point to have two gravitational field values, and this is impossible. More generally, physical magnitudes within a determinable family, like 1kg mass and 2kg mass, exclude one another. Given this fact and the fact that nomic necessity is alethic, it follows that it is impossible for two points to stand in more than one distance relation.
Of course, the spacetime functionalist is left with the unexplained incompatibility of physical magnitudes. But so too is the spacetime primitivist. The spacetime functionalist has no need, unlike the primitivist, to additionally stipulate that constraints like the triangle inequality hold.45
Spacetime primitivists must posit brute necessary connections between the basic building blocks of the world, whereas these connections emerge naturally given spacetime functionalism of spacetime. This is another reason to prefer spacetime functionalism.
5 The Argument from Parsimony
The argument from parsimony is simple. Spacetime functionalism attributes less structure to the world than spacetime primitivism. All else equal, we should prefer theories that attribute less structure to the world. So, all else equal, we should prefer spacetime functionalism over spacetime primitivism.
Of course, all else is only equal if spacetime functionalism is able to explain our evidence just as well as spacetime primitivism. This section will present two arguments in favor of this claim. The first argument will pursue an analogy between absolute velocities and spacetime primitivism which gives us reasons to think primitive facts about space and time are undetectable and therefore empirically redundant. The second argument makes the perhaps surprising claim that our apparent evidence does not include facts about the world’s spatiotemporal structure. Since we should believe the best explanation of our apparent evidence, we should adopt spacetime functionalism.
My first case against spacetime primitivism is analogous to the case against endorsing facts about absolute velocity in the context of Newtonian gravitational mechanics (NGM).
You are moving at different speeds relative to different things. You are stationary with respect to your armchair, moving at about 66,500 mph around the sun, and at about 515,000 mph around the center of the Milky Way. But how fast are you really going? Do you also have an absolute velocity in addition to all these relative velocities?
The consensus among philosophers of science is that we should think not. As Newton himself was aware, what the laws of NGM say about how things in a system interact is completely independent of how fast the system is moving. But this means that even if you have an absolute velocity, it is impossible to detect it. The fact that absolute velocities are undetectable shows that we don’t need them to make sense of the world: they are empirically redundant. Since we should prefer theories that attribute less structure to the world, we should prefer an account of the world that does not recognize absolute velocities.46
Why aren’t absolute velocities detectable? On a natural way of thinking about detectability, for a physical quantity \(q\) to be detectable requires that there is a measuring procedure for \(q\): a process whose outputs (a) are reliably correlated with the value of \(q\) and (b) are accessible to us, so that the procedure allows us to form reliable beliefs about the value of \(q\).47 For example, a measurement procedure might correlate the value of \(q\) with the position of a dial in some measuring device, or what is displayed on a computer screen, or the arrangement of ink particles on a piece of paper, so that by observing the dial, computer screen or paper, we can form reliable beliefs about \(q\).
If a quantity \(q\) is detectable by any means then we can argue that in particular there must be a measurement procedure that correlates the value of \(q\) with the positions of material bodies; for example, the positions of ink particles on a piece of paper. After all, if there is any measurement procedure for \(q\) that allows me to form reliable beliefs about \(q\), then I could decide to write down the content of my beliefs on a piece of paper, and so the procedure that includes my recording the result on paper will itself be a reliable measurement procedure.48
But given NGM it is impossible for there to be a measurement procedure like this for absolute velocity! Suppose there were such a procedure and that it is carried out by Sally the scientist. Sally writes down the result on a piece of paper: My absolute velocity is 5 mph. Now imagine a world that is just like ours, except that everything is moving 1000 miles an hour faster in a certain direction. The two worlds agree on the relative motions and positions of every object, and Sally therefore writes down My absolute velocity is 5 mph. in this world too. But Sally’s absolute velocity is different in the two worlds, and so the measurement procedure must have produced a false result in at least one of them. So the procedure can’t have been reliable after all.
This suggests the following necessary condition for some quantity to be detectable:
P1. A quantity \(q\) is detectable in \(w\) only if there is a measurement procedure for \(q\) in \(w\).
Since there is no measurement procedure for absolute velocities in NGM, absolute velocities are undetectable.
However, for some quantity \(q\) to be detectable it is not sufficient for there to be a measurement procedure for \(q\). Consider the hypothesis—(Stationary)—that there are facts about absolute velocities but the laws specify that the center of mass of the universe is stationary. There is an measurement procedure for absolute velocities given (Stationary): to find the absolute velocity of some body, simply find its motion relative to the center of mass of the universe.
But there is an important sense in which absolute velocities would still be undetectable given (Stationary). For the measurement procedure described above is only a reliable measurement procedure for absolute velocities if the laws are those of (Stationary). So our having evidence concerning the absolute velocities of things depends on our having evidence that the laws are those of (Stationary). But we don’t have any such evidence, since the world according to (Stationary) is indiscernible from a world in which there are no absolute velocities and the laws are simply those of NGM.49
Consider the theory—(Goblin)—that consists of NGM together with the stipulation that it is physically necessary that there is an invisible, massless goblin collocated with each massive object. It’s extremely natural to think that we should give (Goblin) lower credence because it posits things, goblins, that aren’t needed to explain the data. But according to (P1), if (Goblin) were true then goblins would be detectable: simply locate the massive objects and infer the existence of goblins there. So if (P1) were correct then we could not argue against Goblin on the grounds that the theory contains redundant structure, since goblin-free theories fail to account for all the detectable facts. But this isn’t right.
The general point is that in order for something to be detectable, not only must there be laws that allow us to implement a measuring procedure, we must also know what the laws are that govern our measuring procedure. This suggests that we adopt a more general principle concerning detectability:
P2. If there is a measurement procedure for some quantity \(q\) if the laws are \(L\), but not if the laws are \(L\*\), and we have no evidence that the laws are \(L\) rather than \(L\*\), then \(q\) is undetectable.
This principle correctly predicts that even if (Stationary) is true, absolute velocities are undetectable, and that goblins are undetectable even if (Goblin) is true.
The fact that absolute velocities are empirically undetectable shows that we don’t need facts about absolute velocities to make sense of the world; the extra spacetime structure required to make sense of them is superfluous structure.
The spacetime primitivist holds that there are primitive facts about the spatiotemporal arrangement of the world. I will now argue that facts like these are just like absolute velocities. Worlds that differ only in how things are arranged in spacetime are indiscernible, and so we don’t need primitive spacetime facts to make sense of the world. Spacetime primitivism is committed to redundant structure, for the additional fundamental facts it requires perform no explanatory work.
The argument from redundancy against spacetime primitivism is analogous to the case against positing facts about absolute velocities:
(S1) Spacetime functionalism attributes less structure to the world than spacetime primitivism.
(S2) Ceteris paribus, if two theories are both empirically adequate we should prefer the theory that attributes the least structure to the world.
(S3) Spacetime primitivism and spacetime functionalism are both empirically adequate.
(S4) So, ceteris paribus, we should prefer spacetime functionalism to primitivism.
This argument is valid, and so it remains only to defend the premises.
As for (S1), we could appeal to a modal test for when one theory attributes more structure than another. The claim that endorsing absolute velocities requires extra structure is typically motivated in this way: if there are absolute velocities then there are possibilities that differ only in that everything is moving at a different constant velocity. Similarly, if spacetime primitivism is correct then the actual world and the shrinking world are distinct possibilities. But this is not so according to the spacetime functionalist. Since spacetime functionalism ignores distinctions recognized by spacetime primitivism, spacetime primitivism contains extra structure.
But this modal test is at best a useful heuristic. For consider someone who believes that there are absolute velocities but denies the relevant claims about possibility. For example, as Dasgupta (2013) points out, she might believe that Spinoza was right and there is only one possibility, the actual one. Or she may just endorse (Stationary). A spacetime primitivist could deny that the shrinking world and the actual world are distinct possibilities on similar grounds. But surely these quirky modal beliefs are simply irrelevant to how much structure a theory attributes to the world. A better test is simply to look at the fundamental facts the theories posit. After all, attributing excess structure is a matter of what the world is actually like, not what it could have been like. The spacetime primitivist recognizes all the fundamental facts the functionalist does, and more besides: primitive facts about the spacetemporal arrangement of things. So spacetime primitivism attributes more structure to the world than spacetime functionalism.50
I take the principle expressed in (S2) to be ubiquitous in both scientific and common sense reasoning, and enshrined in inference to the best explanation. (S2) is not the claim that simpler hypotheses are always better; just that, faced with two hypotheses that are otherwise equally worthy of belief, we should prefer the one that attributes less structure to the world.
On to (S3). The case for thinking that spacetime functionalism is empirically adequate is analogous to the case of absolute velocity. Since absolute velocities are undetectable, an account of the world that doesn’t recognize absolute velocities is alike in all detectable respects with an account that does, and so both theories are empirically adequate as long as one is.
I will argue that primitive spacetime facts are undetectable, and since spacetime functionalism agrees with spacetime primtivism on all the detectable facts, spacetime functionalism is empirically adequate if spacetime primitivism is.
Why think primitive spacetime facts are undetectable? Well, consider whether there is a measurement procedure for distance facts, for example. There must be a procedure that, given two points \(p_1\), \(p_2\), results in a recording of “\(p_1\) is \(x\) meters from \(p_2\)” only if \(p_1\) is in fact \(x\) meters from \(p_2\). Suppose that placing the end of some measuring tape next to one point, holding the tape taut so that it lies on the second point, and recording the number on the tape adjacent to the second point is such a measurement procedure.
Suppose we try to measure my height by this method. Now consider the halved or shrinking worlds described in the previous section, in which my height is different from what it actually is. Since these worlds have the same causal structure as the actual world, they agree about the output of the measurement procedure. So in order for the tape measure to give me evidence about my height I need to have evidence that the laws are those of the actual world and not those of the halved world or the shrinking world. But we don’t have any such evidence. These worlds have the same causal structure, and so they are perfectly indiscernible. The same things happen, and for the same reasons. After all, suppose you actually form the belief that there is beer in the fridge on the basis of your perceptual evidence. Then in any world with the same causal structure as the actual world, a purely qualitative duplicate of you forms the same belief on the basis of seeing a purely qualitative duplicate of the beer (and drinks it for the same reason!)
So for every world recognized by the spacetime primitivist there is a an empirically equivalent world recognized by the spacetime functionalist. Thus spacetime primitivism is empirically adequate only if both theories are. This completes the defence of premise (S3) in the argument. Even though spacetime functionalism attributes less structure to the world than spacetime primitivism it is still able to account for the data. The extra structure of spacetime primitivism is redundant structure.
So much for the argument from undetectability. I will now present a related but different argument for the claim that spacetime primitivism is committed to redundant structure. It is clear enough that the spacetime functionalist attributes less structure to the world than the spacetime primitivist. But the crucial question is whether she can get away with less. Can we explain our evidence with the sparser resources of spacetime functionalism?
Not, of course, if our evidence includes facts about how things are arranged in space and time. For according to the spacetime functionalist worlds with the same causal structure are the same world, but (at least, according to the spacetime primitivist) they disagree radically about how things are arranged in space and time. Since spacetime functionalism is only worthy of belief if it is capable of explaining our evidence, the spacetime functionalist must argue that our evidence does not include facts about how things are arranged in space and time.
I’ll now argue for for this claim. Well, not quite—I will argue that in the sense of evidence that is relevant in metaphysics, our evidence does not include facts about the spatiotemporal arrangement of the world.
There is a close connection between the concepts of evidence and rationality: to believe rationally is to accord credence in proportion to the evidence. So theories of evidence make predictions about rational belief.
Because of this many externalist theories of evidence apparently undergenerate predections of rational belief. Consider someone whose internal mental life is indistinguishable from your own but who, sadly, is a massively deceived brain in a vat. Many externalists insist that you have evidence your unhappily situated twin lacks (otherwise on what grounds do we believe we ourselves are not in the bad case?) For example, Williamson (2000) holds that our evidence just consists in what we know. If I know that I have hands, then my having hands is part of my evidence; my twin will clearly lack this evidence). But if part of what makes my belief that I have hands rational is something that my deceived twin lacks, it would seem that my twin’s belief that he has hands is not rational (or at least, if it is, then the rationality of my own belief is oddly overdetermined.) But there is something very compelling about that the thought that if one of us is rational, we both are—after all, our mental lives are indiscernible, and we reason in identical ways.51
We should believe the propositions supported by our evidence. If externalism about evidence is right, then there is a sense that my twin should not believe he has hands. Perhaps there is a sense of “should”, associated with a conception of evidence, on which this is right. But it seems extremely hard to deny that there is also a sense in which, if I ought to believe I have hands, then my twin ought to believe he has hands too. And associated with this notion of rationality there is a conception of evidence on which we have the same evidence. Denote this concept evidence\(_Int\). (For a useful foil, call the Williamson notion of evidence\(_Ext\).)52
While I’m happy to grant the existence of multiple conceptions of evidence, it also seems clear that only one of these conceptions can usefully inform deliberation. Imagine my deceived twin deliberating about whether or not to believe he has hands. It does him little good to be told: believe whatever is support by the things you know!, for what he is deliberating about is exactly whether he knows the things that would be count in favor of believing he has hands.
The concept of evidence\(_Ext\) seems to undergenerate rational belief in the case of my deceived twin. But it also appears to overgenerate rational belief.
Recall (Goblin), the theory that the laws are those of NGM together with the stipulation that there is an invisible, massless goblin collocated with every massless object. Suppose that (Goblin) is true. Now consider Greta, who believes (Goblin.) Surely we think that Greta is being irrational—she should reflect on her beliefs and realize that there is a simpler theory that explains her evidence just as well as (Goblin)—namely, NGM.
But if we should believe whatever explains our evidence\(_Ext\), Greta should believe there are goblins. This is because she does know where the goblins are—she is very good at locating massive objects, and very good a correctly inferring the existence of a goblin there. The whereabouts of goblins are therefore part of her evidence, and so she should reject the Goblin-free theory on the ground that it can’t explain her evidence.
Similarly, consider Sid, who believes (Stationary) and is in a world where (Stationary) is true. Assuming he possesses the relevant astronomical information and makes the appropriate inferences, Sid does know about absolute velocities. If he is rational in rejecting theories that fail to account for her evidence, he is rational in maintaining his belief in Newtonian absolute space. But intuitively this isn’t right; there is at least a sense of “ought” in which Sid ought not to believe in absolute velocities.53
Again, we can note that considerations about what our evidence\(_Ext\) consists of will not, in general, be very helpful in deliberation. Imagine Greta and Sid deliberating about whether or not to believe in the inflated or the simpler theories they are considering. It is no help to admonish them to believe whatever explains their evidence\(_Ext\), for the theories themselves have different consequences for their evidence\(_Ext\) consists of.
This suggests the following moral. If you are unsure about what to believe, the best piece of useful advice that can inform your deliberation is: believe the best explanation of your evidence\(_Int\). This is precisely the situation with the debate between the spacetime primitivist and the spacetime functionalist. Which theory is correct will dictate which propositions are included in our evidence\(_Ext\). But just as it was inappropriate for Greta to reject goblin-free theories of the world on the grounds that they fail to explain her evidence, it would be equally inappropriate for you, gentle reader, to reject spacetime functionalism on the grounds that it fails to account for all the facts about how things are arranged in space and time. What matters is that spacetime functionalism explains the appearances, and does so while attributing less structure to the world than spacetime primitivism. This is a count in favor of the theory.
Note that the dispute at issue between spacetime functionalism and the spacetime primitivist is about what we ought to believe, not about what we know, given the beliefs we have. Just as Greta knows where the goblins are, but still shouldn’t believe in them, I grant that if spacetime primitivism were true then we would know how things are arranged in space and time. But this does not yet answer the question of whether or not to believe that spacetime primitivism is true.
A quite different response to the argument from redundancy is that while, all else equal, we should prefer theories that attribute less structure to the world, all else is not equal between spacetime primitivism and spacetime functionalism. By allowing the extra structure required by spacetime primitivism we obtain a theory that is much more explanatory, or otherwise superior, and so the extra structure earns its keep. Spacetime functionalism may attribute less structure to the world, but it is so unwieldy, or disjunctive, or ugly that it is overall unworthy of belief. However, the previous sections, which presented the arguments from explanatory power and metaphysical redundancy, argued that spacetime functionalism is not just theoretically on a par with spacetime primitivism, it is to be preferred precisely because it is explanatorily superior.
6 Conclusion
I hope to have shown in this paper that spacetime functionalism deserves serious consideration as an alternative to spacetime primitivism. This has important implications elsewhere in metaphysics.
I’ll close by mentioning one such issue. The debate over Humeanism is one of the most polarizing in metaphysics. Recall that the Humean reductionist about laws cannot be a spacetime functionalist. This means we are faced with the question of how the merits of non-Humean spacetime functionalism compares with the merits of Humean spacetime primitivism.
Each of these packages of views takes something as primitive that the other regards as reducible. Moreover, many of the traditional arguments against non-Humeanism are based on considerations that count similarly against spacetime primitivism as well.
For example, one argument against non-Humeanism involves the charge that we lack epistemic access to the non-Humean’s extra machinery, since there are worlds with the same regularities as the actual world but in which this machinery is absent.54 To the extent that one shouldn’t argue for metaphysical conclusions from epistemic premises, we can reframe this concern as one that is really about redundant structure: we can make sense of the world without the non-Humean’s extra machinery, claims the Humean, and so we have no reason to posit this extra structure.55 I have argued that these kinds of considerations also form the basis of an argument against spacetime primitivism.
A distinct kind of concern about non-Humeanism is that it is mysterious. One way of presenting this worry is that while the Humean has a story to tell about why laws play the epistemic role they in fact do—for example, why they back explanations, counterfactuals, and induction—the non-Humean must simply stipulate that laws are fit to play these roles.56 A related argument is that the non-Humean account is unduly mysterious because it is committed to unexplained necessary connections. This charge is based on the claim that it must be simply postulated that the non-Humean’s laws entail the regularities they are invoked to explain.57 I have argued that precisely analogous considerations count equally against spacetime primitivism.
This suggests that the question of whether or not Humeanism is correct is left undecided by the arguments typically marshaled in favor of Humeanism. Proper way to assess the relative merits of Humeanism and non-Humeanism, it seems, must involve a comparison of the overall packages of views in metaphysics with which they may be combined. That, however, is a project for another day.
Note Added, by Eddy Keming Chen and Dean Zimmerman
Marco Dees wrote the first version of this paper in 2015, as part of his dissertation submitted for his Ph.D. in philosophy at Rutgers University, New Brunswick. This version of the paper was finished before his untimely death in 2018. We believe that it contains insights that will be of interest to the philosophical community, and we were pleased when Marco’s family asked us to explore whether it would be possible for it to be published in an academic journal. Marco defends the idea that the spatiotemporal structure of the world is not fundamental, but is instead grounded in the role spacetime regions play in laws of nature. We are glad that the paper has been, after peer review, accepted by dialectica. Given the current state of the literature, it would have been better to call Marco’s view “spacetime causal functionalism”, in order to make clear the contrast between his theory and versions of spacetime functionalism as defended, for example, by Eleanor Knox in the context of general relativity and by Nick Huggett, Vincent Lam, and Christian Wüthrich in the context of quantum gravity. It is likely that, given the opportunity for revision, Marco would have taken the opportunity to compare his causal functionalism with these other forms of spacetime functionalism. In the end, we decided to leave the paper as Marco had written it, hoping that others will be inspired to work out the comparisons.