Skip To Content
Cookies help us deliver our services. By using our services, you agree to our use of cookies.
Dialectica 75(3)

Sensitivity and Inductive Knowledge Revisited

Beta version. This is a page made for testing purposes. For the official version of the article, please visit to OJS webpage at https://dialectica.philosophie.ch/.
    Abstract

    The orthodox view about sensitivity and induction has it that beliefs formed via induction are insensitive. Since inductive knowledge is highly plausible, this problem is usually regarded as a reductio argument against sensitivity accounts of knowledge. Some adherents of sensitivity defend sensitivity against this objection, for example by considering backtracking interpretations of counterfactuals. All these extant views about sensitivity and induction have to be revised since the problem of sensitivity and induction is a different one. Regardless of whether we allow backtracking interpretations of counterfactuals, some instances of induction yield insensitive beliefs whereas others yield sensitive ones. These results are too heterogeneous to provide a plausible sensitivity account of inductive knowledge. Induction remains a serious problem for sensitivity accounts of knowledge.

    1 Sensitivity and induction: the discussion so far

    Nozick suggests that if S knows that \(p\), then S’s belief that \(p\) tracks truth. He thinks that subjunctive conditionals can best capture this truth-tracking relation. Moreover, he argues that we have to take the belief-forming method into account. Nozick (1981, 179) provides the following definition of knowing via a method:

    S knows, via method (or way of believing) M, that \(p\) iff (1) \(p\) is true (2) S believes, via method or way of coming to believe M, that \(p\) (3) In the nearest possible worlds where \(p\) is false and where S uses M to arrive at a belief whether (or not) \(p\), S does not believe, via M, that \(p\) (4) In the nearest possible worlds where \(p\) is true and where S uses M to arrive at a belief whether (or not) \(p\), S believes, via M, that \(p\)1

    Condition (3) is the sensitivity condition, which I will focus on here, and condition (4) is the adherence condition.2 Nozick formulates these modal conditions on knowledge as subjunctive conditionals, but he analyzes their truth conditions in terms of possible worlds. For the sake of convenience, and in accordance with the literature, I will use possible world terminology for formulating conditions (3) and (4). For the purposes of this paper, nothing hinges on this decision, as we acquire the same results for sensitivity and induction when talking in terms of subjunctive conditionals.3

    Sensitivity accounts of knowledge face several major problems. First, it has been claimed that they preclude us from having inductive knowledge, as Vogel (1987, 1999) and Sosa (1999) contend. Second, they lead to implausible instances of closure failure as Kripke (2011) argues.4 Third, Sosa (1999) and Vogel (2000) argued that sensitivity faces severe problems concerning higher-order knowledge about the truth of one’s own beliefs. In this paper, I will focus on the first objection.5 However, we will see in the last section that the problem of inductive knowledge has structural similarities to the problem of higher-order knowledge.

    Despite the well-known challenges that sensitivity accounts of knowledge face, the sensitivity principle is intuitively appealing, leading to a “second wave” of sensitivity accounts, as Becker and Black (2012) label it. These accounts aim at defending a sensitivity-based theory of knowledge that avoids the problems that have been raised for Nozick’s (1981) original account.6 Accordingly, the results about sensitivity and induction are not only relevant for Nozick’s original theory but also for these descendants.7

    Vogel and Sosa argue for the claim that making sensitivity a necessary condition on knowledge rules out inductive knowledge by means of examples; they provide cases where a subject plausibly knows via induction although her belief is insensitive. Here are two cases:

    Chute. On his way to the elevator, Ernie releases a trash bag down the chute from his high-rise condo. Walking along the street Ernie thinks about the trash and forms the belief that the trash is in the basement. Plausibly, Ernie knows that his bag is in the basement. But what if, having been released, it still (incredibly) were not to arrive there? That presumably would be because it had been snagged somehow in the chute on the way down (an incredibly rare occurrence), or some such happenstance. But none of these would affect Ernie’s belief, so he would still believe that the bag has arrived in the basement. His belief seems not to be sensitive, therefore, but constitutes knowledge anyhow, and can correctly be said to do so. (See Sosa 1999, 145–146)

    Heartbreaker. Sixty golfers are entered in the Wealth and Privilege Invitational Tournament. The course has a short but difficult hole, known as the “Heartbreaker.” Before the round begins, Jonathan thinks that, surely, not all sixty players will get a hole-in-one on the “Heartbreaker.” (See Vogel 1999, 165)8

    These are cases of beliefs that are based on inductive reasoning, more specifically, inductive reasoning about particulars, as Vogel puts it.9 He argues that knowledge about particulars via inductive reasoning is highly plausible. Intuitively, Ernie knows that the trash is in the basement, and Jonathan knows that not all sixty players will get a hole-in-one. However, in each case the target beliefs are insensitive. Consequently, sensitivity is not necessary for knowledge.

    Sosa and Vogel argue against sensitivity accounts of knowledge by presenting examples of insensitive inductive beliefs that plausibly constitute knowledge. They need not argue for the stronger claim that any belief formed via induction is insensitive to make their point. The weaker claim that there are some plausible cases of inductive knowledge that involve insensitive beliefs is sufficient for their purpose. Nevertheless, the stronger view that any belief formed via induction is insensitive is the dominant one in the current debate.10

    Sosa’s and Vogel’s line of argumentation against sensitivity accounts of knowledge is not unopposed. One standard defense of sensitivity is proposed by Becker (2007). He accepts the view that induction yields insensitive beliefs, but he argues that this does not create a devastating objection to sensitivity accounts of knowledge. He admits that if we know propositions \(p\)1\(p\)n, then we do not have inductive knowledge that \(p\)n+1 is true. However, we still have knowledge about the probability of \(p\)n+1.11 Thus, our view about knowledge via induction rests on a confusion according to Becker. We cannot have knowledge via induction that \(p\)n+1; what we do know are propositions in the neighborhood of this proposition. Becker’s account not only rejects inductive knowledge but also provides an explanation of our mistaken intuition that we can have this kind of knowledge. However, knowledge via induction is widely accepted. Accordingly, most philosophers are presumably not willing to bite the bullet of rejecting inductive knowledge for the gain of acquiring a sensitivity-based account of knowledge. We will take up Becker’s account later and see that his solution faces additional problems.

    Vogel, Sosa, and Becker agree that the subjects’ beliefs in cases like Chute and Heartbreaker are insensitive, but draw conflicting conclusions as to whether this claim creates a serious problem for sensitivity accounts of knowledge. Until recently, the view that induction yields insensitive beliefs has remained unchallenged. Wallbridge (2018) takes up this objection to sensitivity accounts of knowledge and argues that properly understood, the purported counterexamples fail to succeed because the beliefs formed via induction are actually sensitive, not insensitive. Focusing on Sosa’s chute case, Wallbridge argues that Ernie sensitively believes that the rubbish is in the basement. He claims that in some cases, in order to avoid “miracles”, i.e. events that would not easily have happened, counterfactuals have to be interpreted as backtracking. According to a backtracking interpretation, counterfactual conditionals can be evaluated without keeping the past fixed until the time at which the counterfactual antecedent obtains. Wallbridge argues that, according to this backtracking analysis, Ernie’s belief is sensitive.12 He suggests that other examples presented by Vogel (1987, 1999) and Pritchard (2012) can be analyzed analogously. Wallbridge is not particularly clear about his conclusion. In the abstract, he claims to show that inductive knowledge is sensitive. In the conclusion, Wallbridge (2018, 8) makes the weaker claim that “there are cases of sensitive inductive knowledge” and leaves the reader with a challenge, concluding that “if there are cases of insensitive inductive knowledge then they have yet to be pointed out.”

    In Section 2, I will show that the situation concerning induction and sensitivity is more subtle than opponents and defenders of sensitivity accounts of knowledge claim it to be. Some inductive processes yield sensitive beliefs, others yield insensitive beliefs, regardless of whether we opt for a backtracking or a non-backtracking interpretation of counterfactual conditionals. In Section 3, I will argue that this is problematic since the subjects in the cases presented are concerning inductive reasoning intuitively in similarly good epistemic situations. Hence, sensitivity accounts of knowledge are committed to making implausibly heterogeneous predictions about the knowledge status of subjects who believe via induction.

    2 Sensitive and insensitive induction

    In this section, I will discuss instances of enumerative and temporal induction and backtracking and non-backtracking interpretations of counterfactual conditionals. First, let me make some preliminary remarks about backtracking and non-backtracking counterfactuals. Lewis (1973) distinguishes between backtracking and non-backtracking counterfactuals. Non-backtracking counterfactuals keep the past fixed until the time at which the counterfactual antecedent obtains, whereas backtracking counterfactuals do not.13 He argues that only non-backtracking counterfactuals can be used for analyzing causal dependencies. For example, in order to determine whether event \(c\) caused event \(e\), we consider those possible worlds that are identical with the actual world until the time where \(c\) does not obtain.14

    In this paper, I will remain neutral about whether counterfactuals are correctly interpreted as backtracking or non-backtracking. Rather, I will investigate the consequences of these two interpretations for sensitivity accounts of knowledge. Let me emphasize the point of considering backtracking counterfactuals. We can say that whether S’s induction-based belief is sensitive depends on whether “the minimal ‘change’ from truth to falsity of \(p\) keeps the inductive evidence for \(p\) intact.”15 In terms of possible worlds, the sensitivity of S’s belief depends on whether the inductive evidence is available to S in the nearest possible worlds where \(p\) is false. If we interpret counterfactuals exclusively as non-backtracking, then we only consider possible worlds that do not differ from the actual world until the point at which the counterfactual antecedent obtains. If we allow for backtracking interpretations of counterfactuals, then we need not keep the past fixed until that point. Hence, backtracking or non-backtracking interpretations make a difference concerning which nearest possible worlds are considered and consequently whether a belief is judged to be sensitive or not.

    In the following, I will present and analyze further cases of induction. We will see that some cases yield insensitive beliefs whereas others yield sensitive beliefs, regardless of whether counterfactuals can be backtracking or not. I will distinguish between enumerative induction where we draw an inference from objects \(o\)1-\(o\)n to \(o\)n+1 and temporal induction where we draw an inference about an object \(o\) from time \(t\)1-\(t\)n to \(t\)n+1.16 In each of these cases, the method of belief formation in question is induction.17 Moreover, the cases have to be understood in a way such that the subjects are intuitively in equally good epistemic positions concerning the inductive conclusion in that (1) the evidence for believing the premises is equally strong; (2) the numbers of cases \(n\) observed is equally large (or the time interval observed is equally long); (3) the relevant similarity between the induced case cn+1 and observed cases c1 to cn is equally strong (or the similarity between the basic conditions for \(o\) of the induced time point \(t\) and the observed interval \(i\)); (4) there are no rebutting or undercutting defeaters available to the subjects; and (5) the predicates involved are equally projectible. Take, first, the following example of enumerative induction that yields an insensitive belief:

    Raven (enumerative induction). Carl observes that raven1–ravenn is black and infers that ravenn+1, which he has not observed, is black. Ravens are typically black, though not necessarily, since there also exist rare mutations like albino ravens. In the nearest possible worlds where ravenn+1 is not black, it is such a rare mutation. However, raven1-ravenn is black in these nearest possible worlds and Carl believes via observation of raven1-ravenn and induction that ravenn+1 is black. Thus, his belief that ravenn+1 is black is insensitive.

    This analysis holds independently of whether counterfactuals are allowed to be backtracking or not. In both cases, the nearest possible worlds where ravenn+1 is not black are such that it is an albino raven but where raven1–ravenn is black. In these possible worlds, Carl still believes via induction that ravenn+1 is black. Hence, his belief is insensitive. Thus, in RAVEN, a case of enumerative induction, the subject believes insensitively, regardless of whether we allow backtracking interpretations of counterfactuals or not.18

    Notably, a similar case of temporal induction yields a different outcome:

    Blackbird (temporal induction). Miles observes that blackbirdn has been black until yesterday and believes via induction that blackbirdn is black right now.

    Non-backtracking: We only consider the nearest possible worlds where blackbirdn is not black right now, and, hence, worlds where blackbirdn has been black until yesterday. We ignore possible worlds where blackbirdn changed its color earlier and worlds where it has never been black. In the nearest possible worlds considered Miles believes via observation and induction that blackbirdn is black right now. Hence, his belief is insensitive.

    Backtracking: If counterfactuals are backtracking the situation is different. In this case, the nearest possible worlds where blackbirdn is not black right now are presumably such that it is an albino blackbirdn that has been white all the time. They are not worlds where it changed the color since yesterday. Accordingly, in the nearest possible worlds where blackbirdn is not black right now Miles does not believe via observation and induction that it is black right now. Thus, Miles’ inductive belief that blackbirdn is black right now is sensitive.19

    So far we have seen that in the enumerative induction case of Raven, Carl’s belief is insensitive no matter whether counterfactuals can be backtracking or not. However, in Blackbird, a case of temporal induction, Miles’ belief is insensitive if counterfactuals are non-backtracking but sensitive if they are backtracking. At this point, one might suppose that enumerative induction is typically insensitive whereas the sensitivity of temporal induction depends on whether we opt for a non-backtracking interpretation or a backtracking one. However, this generalization is incorrect as the following cases will show. Take a second instance of enumerative induction that delivers sensitive beliefs in case of non-backtracking and backtracking counterfactuals:

    Examiner (enumerative induction). Ina is a lazy examiner. When she has received all the exams she throws a dice and all the examinees get the same grade. For a particular test, she throws a 2 and, accordingly, marks all exams with B. Rachel is an examinee and does not know Ina’s habits. Rachel asks numerous peers about their grades. Among them are peers of whom she knows that they were better prepared than herself and peers of whom she knows that they were worse prepared. All peers report that they got a B. Rachel forms the belief that she also got a B. The nearest possible worlds where Rachel does not get a B are such that Ina’s dice throw delivered a different result than 2 and all students got a different grade than B, but the same one. In these possible worlds, Rachel does not believe via testimony and induction that she got a B. Thus, her belief that she got a B on the exam is sensitive.

    The grades of all students are determined at the same time. Thus, no matter whether counterfactuals can be backtracking or not, the nearest possible worlds where Rachel does not get a B are such that all the other students do not get a B. In these possible worlds, Rachel does not believe via testimony and induction that she got a B. Thus, Rachel’s belief is sensitive, regardless of whether counterfactuals can be backtracking or not. Raven and Examiner are both cases of enumerative induction. In Raven, the target belief is insensitive, no matter whether counterfactuals can be backtracking or not, and in Examiner, it is sensitive in both cases.

    So far we have reflected on one case of temporal induction, Blackbird, where the belief is insensitive with a non-backtracking interpretation of counterfactuals and sensitive with a backtracking interpretation. We will now see that temporal induction can deliver different sensitivity results in different cases. Let’s sketch a further case:

    T – shirt (temporal induction). Sarah has seen Tim wearing a red T-shirt the whole day until 30 minutes ago and forms the inductive belief that Tim is wearing a red T-shirt right now.

    Is Sarah’s belief that Tim is wearing a red T-shirt right now sensitive? This depends on how we fill in the details. Let us consider two different scenarios:

    Scenario 1: Tim and Sarah are on a hiking trail and they split thirty minutes ago. Sarah has seen Tim wearing a red T-shirt the whole day and forms the inductive belief that Tim is wearing a red T-shirt right now. Tim does not have another T-shirt with him. Thus, he could not easily get a fresh T-shirt. Suppose further that Tim accidentally grabbed a red T-shirt in the morning, but that he might easily have grabbed a T-shirt of a different color. If counterfactuals can be backtracking, then the nearest possible worlds where it is false that Tim is wearing a red T-shirt right now are such that he grabbed a T-shirt of any other color in the morning. In these possible worlds, Sarah does not believe via observation that Tim was wearing a red T-shirt until thirty minutes ago and, therefore, does not believe via induction that he is wearing a red T-shirt right now. Thus, her belief is sensitive. If counterfactuals can only be non-backtracking, then we only consider possible worlds where Tim recently changed his T-shirt. In this case, Sarah’s belief that Tim is wearing a T-shirt right now formed via observation and induction is insensitive. Hence, for Scenario 1, we acquire the same result as for Blackbird—a non-backtracking interpretation of counterfactuals implies insensitive beliefs, and a backtracking interpretation sensitive beliefs.

    Scenario 2: Sarah and Tim were on a hiking trail until 30 minutes ago where Tim was wearing a red T-shirt. In fact, for security concerns, Tim only wears red T-shirts for hiking. Thus, it is not easily possible that he had a non-red T-shirt for hiking. After the hiking trail, Sarah and Tim split and Tim walks downtown for a drink. Sarah has seen Tim wearing a red T-shirt the whole day until 30 minutes ago and forms the inductive belief that Tim is wearing a red T-shirt right now. If counterfactuals can only be non-backtracking, then we only consider possible worlds where Tim recently changed his T-shirt. In these possible worlds, Sarah believes via observation and temporal induction that he is wearing a red T-shirt right now and, consequently, her belief is insensitive. However, even if we allow for backtracking counterfactuals, then the nearest possible worlds where Tim is not wearing a red T-shirt right now are such that he changed it recently downtown, given Tim’s strict habit of only wearing red T-shirts for hiking.20 Again, Sarah believes that Tim is wearing a red T-shirt right now and her inductive belief turns out to be insensitive.

    In both scenarios, a non-backtracking interpretation of counterfactuals yields insensitive beliefs, but if we allow for backtracking interpretations, then Scenario 1 yields a sensitive belief whereas Scenario 2 yields an insensitive belief. In this respect, whether one’s belief is sensitive in cases of temporal induction depends on how the cases are spelled out in detail.

    We can now summarize the acquired results about sensitivity and induction: Raven is a case of enumerative induction. Carl’s belief that ravenn+1 is black is insensitive regardless of whether counterfactual conditionals can be backtracking or not. Examiner is a further case of enumerative induction. However, Sarah’s belief that she got a B for the exam is sensitive regardless of whether counterfactuals can be backtracking or not. Blackbird is a case of temporal induction. Miles’s belief that blackbirdn is black is insensitive if counterfactuals can only be non-backtracking, but it is sensitive if they can be backtracking. As for T-shirt, a further case of temporal induction, sensitivity depends on how we fill in the details. In Scenario 1 and 2, Sarah’s belief that Tim is wearing a red T-shirt right now is insensitive if counterfactuals can only be non-backtracking. If they can be backtracking, then her belief is sensitive in Scenario 1 but insensitive in Scenario 2. These results are captured in table 1:

    Table 1: Whether the belief is sensitive in non-backtracking and backtracking variants of the four cases.
    Induction type Case Non-backtracking Backtracking
    Enumerative Raven \(-\) \(-\)
    Examiner \(+\) \(+\)
    Temporal Blackbird \(-\) \(+\)
    T-shirt \(-\) \(+/-\)

    Let me provide a more systematic analysis: Suppose S observes that object \(o\) has property F from t1 to tn and believes via temporal induction that \(o\) has property F at tn+1. If we generally accept that counterfactuals can be backtracking, then S’s inductive belief is sensitive only if, in the nearest possible worlds where \(o\) is not F at time tn+1, \(o\) is not F from t1 to tn.21 This is the case if worlds where \(o\) lost property F from tn to tn+1 are more remote than worlds where \(o\) does not have property F from t1 to tn, e.g. if it is more crucial for \(o\) to constantly be F (or to constantly be not-F) from t1 to tn+1 than to be F from t1 to tn, as in Blackbird and Scenario 1 of T-shirt, where Tim does not walk downtown. In Scenario 2, where Tim walks downtown after the hiking trail, the worlds where Tim changed his T-shirt downtown are closer than the worlds where he was not wearing a red T-shirt on the hiking trail. Here, it is more crucial for \(o\) to be F from t1 to tn than it is to be constantly F or constantly not be F from t1 to tn+1. Consequently, Sarah’s belief is insensitive. In contrast, if counterfactuals can only be non-backtracking, then we can only consider possible worlds where \(o\) changed property F from tn to tn+1. In this case, beliefs formed via temporal induction are always insensitive. Thus, despite the heterogeneity of the overall results, at least we can say that temporal induction always yields insensitive beliefs if counterfactuals can only be non-backtracking.

    We obtain slightly different results concerning enumerative induction. If the nearest possible worlds where \(o\)n+1 does not have property F are such that \(o\)1-\(o\)n does not have property F, then S’s belief that \(o\)n+1 is F formed via observation of \(o\)1- \(o\)n and enumerative induction is presumably sensitive.22 This condition is fulfilled if it is rather accidental that \(o\)n+1 is F but characteristic for \(o\)1- \(o\)n+1 that they have the same status of being F (or not being F), as in Examiner. However, if the nearest possible worlds where \(o\)n+1 does not have property F are such that \(o\)1- \(o\)n still has property F, then S’s belief formed via observation and induction is insensitive. This holds for Raven.

    Notably, theories of counterfactuals that allow for non-backtracking counterfactuals and theories that do not deliver the same results for each individual case of enumerative induction, i.e. both types of theories imply that the target belief is sensitive or both theory types imply that it is insensitive. Perhaps we can construct cases of enumerative induction such that backtracking and non-backtracking theories deliver different results with respect to sensitivity, but I suspect that these instances of induction also involve a temporal element.23

    3 Heterogeneity: The problem for sensitivity and induction

    Let me now diagnose what I regard as the real problem of sensitivity and induction. There is at least a tendency among proponents and critics of sensitivity that there is a homogeneous picture of sensitivity and induction. Critics of sensitivity accounts of knowledge, but also some adherents such as Becker, tend to think that induction yields insensitive beliefs whereas Wallbridge suggests that it yields sensitive beliefs. However, none of these opposing views is correct, since some instances of induction yield sensitive beliefs whereas some others yield insensitive ones.

    I developed various cases of enumerative and temporal induction. In each of these cases, the subjects make an empirical observation and draw an inductive inference. Importantly, we intuitively judge that the subjects in these cases are in equally good epistemic positions. This view about the equality of the epistemic positions is also supported when applying plausible parameters for induction. Let me briefly explain. The epistemic force of induction comes in degrees. The epistemic strength of inductive reasoning from cases c1-cn to case cn+1 (or from time interval \(i\) to point in time \(t\)) and whether it can yield justification and knowledge intuitively depends on various factors. The strength of induction depends first on the number \(n\) of cases observed (or on the length of the observed time interval). All else being equal, the larger \(n\) is, the greater the epistemic strength of a particular induction; Secondly, the epistemic strength of induction varies with the relevant similarity between the cases observed and the case induced (or on the relevant similarity between the observed time interval and the point in time induced).24 The more similar cn+1 is to c1-cn in the relevant sense, the stronger the inductive reasoning is. Third, the epistemic strength of inductive reasoning depends on whether there exists a defeater \(d\) for the inductive conclusion, either rebutting or undercutting, such that S is propositionally justified in believing \(d\) and this justification undermines S’s justification in holding an inductive belief about cn+1. Finally, the predicate involved has to be projectible.

    Moreover, the amount of justification for the conclusion of an induction is also affected by the strength of the justification for believing the premises. All else being equal, the stronger the justification for believing the premises, the stronger the justification for believing the inductive conclusion.

    This paper aims at showing that sensitivity accounts of knowledge have highly implausible consequences when it comes to inductive knowledge. In order to make this point, it suffices to refer to intuitively plausible criteria for inductive knowledge. We need not develop a detailed theory of induction and confirmation, involving Bayesianism or alternative conceptions.25 For the purposes of this paper, it suffices to accept that in the cases discussed, the inductive reasoning is intuitively of the same epistemic strength according to the plausible parameters specified. That means that the subjects in the cases have equally good evidence about an equally high number of \(n\) cases (or a sufficiently long time interval \(i\)), case cn+1 is equally similar to the observed cases c1-cn, there is no defeater \(d\) for S, rebutting or undercutting, such that S is justified to believe that \(d\) and this justification undermines her inductive justification, and the predicates involved are equally projectible.26

    Since the subjects are intuitively all in equally good epistemic positions, the minimal standards that a theory of knowledge has to fulfill is that it delivers the same outcome with respect to knowledge in all cases discussed. Here there are two options, first, that the subjects know in all cases of induction presented and, second, that they are precluded from knowing in all cases.27 I assume that there is a wide agreement among epistemologists that we can have knowledge via induction. Accordingly, the first, positive option is far more popular than the second, negative one. However, sensitivity accounts of knowledge cannot deliver any of these two uniform pictures.

    Let me explain in more detail. I regard it as an open question whether counterfactual conditionals can only be correctly interpreted as backtracking or also as non-backtracking. However, in any case we acquire an unsatisfactorily heterogeneous picture. Suppose first that counterfactuals can only be non-backtracking. Presumably, temporal induction always provides insensitive beliefs, given a non-backtracking analysis of counterfactuals as in Blackbird and T-shirt. However, some instances of enumerative induction can yield sensitive beliefs, e.g. Examiner, but some others not, e.g. Raven. Thus, according to a sensitivity account of knowledge, S does not know in Raven, Blackbird, and T-shirt but knows in Examiner, given that counterfactuals can only be non-backtracking.

    This result is counterintuitive since the epistemic position of the subject is intuitively equally good in all four cases. Suppose now that counterfactuals can be backtracking. In this case, Examiner, Blackbird, and Scenario 1 of T-shirt yield sensitive beliefs, but Raven and Scenario 2 of T-shirt yield insensitive beliefs. Again, sensitivity accounts of knowledge are committed to accept that the subjects know in the first three cases but not in the latter two.

    Thus, in both cases of backtracking and non-backtracking theories of counterfactuals, some processes of induction yield sensitive beliefs but some others insensitive beliefs. Hence, sensitivity accounts of knowledge deliver in both cases an implausibly heterogeneous picture of inductive knowledge.28 In both cases, we know via some instances of induction but do not know via some other instances. This heterogeneous picture is no less problematic than the orthodox view, dominant so far, that sensitivity accounts of knowledge preclude us from any kind of inductive knowledge.

    These results affect extant pessimistic and optimistic accounts of sensitivity in various ways. The orthodox view about sensitivity and induction is based on cases of insensitive inductive beliefs that plausibly constitute knowledge, as presented by Vogel (1987, 1999) and Sosa (1999). The popular generalization of these cases has it that any instance of induction yields insensitive beliefs and that we cannot have any inductive knowledge according to sensitivity accounts of knowledge. This generalization is incorrect. However, Vogel and Sosa mainly aim at arguing against sensitivity accounts of knowledge by presenting counterexamples of insensitive knowledge via induction. This goal can still be reached by pointing out that sensitivity accounts of knowledge imply that we do not know in some (paradigmatic) instances of induction that plausibly yield knowledge.

    Becker (2007) accepts that induction yields insensitive beliefs but argues that this does not pose a serious problem since we can still acquire knowledge about the probability of the target proposition.29 This is already problematic since knowledge via induction seems highly plausible. Becker suggests that any instance of induction provides insensitive beliefs. What he should say is that in some cases of induction, we have knowledge of the target proposition, but in some very similar cases, we only have knowledge about the probability of the target proposition. This outcome is too heterogeneous to be plausible and, thus, not more convincing than Becker’s original conclusion.

    Wallbridge (2018) claims that inductive knowledge is sensitive, given that we accept backtracking counterfactuals in some contexts, or at least he leaves the reader with the challenge of presenting cases of insensitive induction. He suggests that we should not exclude backtracking counterfactuals in evaluating modal knowledge conditions like sensitivity or safety. In this respect, Wallbridge’s analysis advances the existing debate about sensitivity and induction. However, he does not tell the whole story about sensitivity and induction since his challenge of finding instances of insensitive induction can be easily met. Moreover, sensitivity is not a matter of backtracking or non-backtracking interpretations of counterfactuals, as he suggests, since there are cases of sensitive induction and cases of insensitive induction for backtracking and non-backtracking interpretations.

    Thus, sensitivity accounts of knowledge do not face the problem of precluding us from any inductive knowledge, as the orthodox view suggests, nor is it true that induction typically provides sensitive beliefs, as Wallbridge argues. Rather, some processes of induction yield sensitive beliefs whereas some very similar processes yield insensitive beliefs. Given this heterogeneous outcome, I do not see how a sensitivity account of knowledge can plausibly integrate a theory of inductive knowledge.

    At this point, adherents of sensitivity might stick to their guns and claim that the acquired results about inductive knowledge are correct, since a sensitivity account of knowledge is correct, even though these results seem implausible at first sight. Nozick (1981) himself frequently endorses a similar line of argumentation, as when he argues that knowledge does not transmit via conjunction elimination, a principle that is highly plausible.30 However, such lines of argumentation are usually regarded as a vice of Nozick’s account rather than virtue. Even adherents of sensitivity usually do not choose this strategy when defending sensitivity accounts of knowledge. For example, DeRose (1995) and Roush (2005) develop sensitivity accounts that avoid Nozick’s implausible consequences of closure failure and Adams and Clarke (2005) defend Nozick’s account against Kripke’s (2011) objection by arguing that in Kripke’s particular case knowledge closure is not violated. None of these defenses of sensitivity simply claim that the reductio arguments against sensitivity accounts fail because their highly counterintuitive consequences are the correct ones. This strategy is not more plausible in the case of induction.

    The state of the discussion about sensitivity and induction has evolved as follows. Sosa and Vogel started the discussion by arguing that sensitivity precludes us from any kind of inductive knowledge, or at least from paradigmatic instances of inductive knowledge. Wallbridge objected that inductive beliefs are typically sensitive, providing a rejoinder to the cases presented by Sosa and Vogel. We have seen that neither of these positions is correct, pointing out instead that the relationship between sensitivity and induction is actually quite heterogeneous.

    Interestingly, this development resembles the development of the discussion concerning sensitivity and higher-level knowledge, another purported challenge to sensitivity accounts of knowledge. Sosa (1999) and Vogel (2000) pointed out that one’s beliefs that one does not falsely believe that \(p\) are insensitive. From this, Vogel concludes that sensitivity accounts of knowledge preclude us from any kind of higher-level knowledge while Sosa argues that this fact leads to implausible instances of closure failure since one can know that \(p\) without knowing that one does not falsely believe that \(p\). Becker (2007) and Salerno (2010) respond to these concerns, pointing out that beliefs in weaker propositions with the formal structure \(\lnot\)(B(\(p\)) \(\wedge \lnot p\)) are insensitive but beliefs in the stronger propositions with the formal structure B(\(p\)) \(\wedge p\) or B(\(p\)) \(\wedge \lnot \lnot p\) can be sensitive. They conclude that we can have the relevant kind of higher-level knowledge according to sensitivity accounts. In Melchior (2015), I argue that the outcome that we know stronger higher-level propositions but fail to know weaker higher-level propositions is too heterogeneous to be plausible, calling this the heterogeneity problem for sensitivity accounts.31 Sensitivity does not preclude us from all inductive knowledge, nor does every instance of induction yield sensitive beliefs. In fact, some instances of induction yield sensitive beliefs, but very similar processes of induction lead to insensitive beliefs. We face a further instance of the heterogeneity problem for sensitivity accounts of knowledge when it comes to sensitivity and induction. This supports the view that heterogeneity, along different dimensions, is a characteristic feature of sensitivity and a more systematic problem for sensitivity accounts of knowledge.32

     

    4 Conclusion

    The orthodox view about sensitivity and induction has it that induction always delivers insensitive beliefs. Critics conclude that sensitivity accounts of knowledge are mistaken. Adherents of sensitivity accounts also assume that induction is homogeneous with respect to sensitivity. Becker accepts that any instance of induction is insensitive but argues that we still can have knowledge about the probability of the target proposition via induction. Wallbridge, in contrast, claims that induction yields sensitive beliefs. A careful analysis reveals more differentiated results. Some instances of induction yield sensitive beliefs but some instances in the neighborhood yield insensitive ones, regardless of whether we interpret counterfactuals as backtracking or non-backtracking. Sensitivity accounts of knowledge must, therefore, accept that we can know in some instances of induction but in very similar ones we cannot, although the epistemic situations of the believing subjects are intuitively equally good. These results are too heterogeneous to provide a plausible picture of inductive knowledge in terms of sensitivity.

    References

      Adams, Frederick and Clarke, Murray. 2005. Resurrecting the Tracking Theories.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83(2): 207–221, doi:10.1080/00048400500111030.
      Baumann, Peter. 2012. Nozick’s Defense of Closure.” in The Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology, edited by Kelly Becker and Tim Black, pp. 11–27. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511783630.004.
      Becker, Kelly. 2007. Epistemology Modalized. Routledge Studies in Contemporary Philosophy n. 5. London: Routledge, doi:10.4324/9780203940341.
      Becker, Kelly and Black, Tim, eds. 2012. The Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511783630.
      Bjerring, Jens Christian and Gundersen, Lars Bo. 2020. Higher-Order Knowledge and Sensitivity.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 50(3): 339–349, doi:10.1017/can.2019.36.
      Cogburn, Jon and Roland, Jeffrey W. 2013. Safety and the True-True Problem.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94(2): 246–267, doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.2012.01454.x.
      Crupi, Vincenzo. 2020. Confirmation.” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, California: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language; Information, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/confirmation/.
      DeRose, Keith. 1995. Solving the Skeptical Problem.” The Philosophical Review 104(1): 1–52, doi:10.2307/2186011.
      DeRose, Keith. 2004. Sosa, Safety, Sensitivity, and Skeptical Hypotheses.” in Ernest Sosa and His Critics, edited by John Greco, pp. 22–41. Philosophers and Their Critics. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, doi:10.1002/9780470756140.ch3.
      DeRose, Keith. 2017. The Appearance of Ignorance. Knowledge, Skepticism, and Context, Vol. II. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press, doi:10.1163/22105700-20191398.
      Enoch, David, Spectre, Levi and Fisher, Talia. 2012. Statistical Evidence, Sensitivity, and the Legal Value of Knowledge.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 40(3): 197–224, doi:10.1111/papa.12000.
      Hawthorne, John. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/0199269556.001.0001.
      Hawthorne, John. 2005. The Case for Closure.” in Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, edited by Ernest Sosa and Matthias Steup, 1st ed., pp. 50–81. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy n. 3. Boston, Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishers. Second edition: Steup, Turri and Sosa (2014, 40–55).
      Khoo, Justin. 2017. Backtracking Counterfactuals Revisited.” Mind 126(503): 841–910, doi:10.1093/mind/fzw005.
      Kripke, Saul A. 2011. Nozick on Knowledge.” in Philosophical Troubles, pp. 162–224. Collected Papers n. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199730155.003.0007.
      Lewis, David. 1973. Counterfactuals. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Cited after republication as Lewis (2001).
      Luper, Steven. 1984. The Epistemic Predicament: Knowledge, Nozickian Tracking, and Scepticism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62(1): 26–49. Published under the name “Luper-Foy”, doi:10.1080/00048408412341241.
      McGlynn, Aidan. 2012. The Problem of True-True Counterfactuals.” Analysis 72(2): 276–285, doi:10.1093/analys/ans046.
      Melchior, Guido. 2014. A Generality Problem for Bootstrapping and Sensitivity .” Croatian Journal of Philosophy 14(40): 31–47.
      Melchior, Guido. 2015. The Heterogeneity Problem for Sensitivity Accounts.” Episteme 12(4): 479–496, doi:10.1017/epi.2015.31.
      Melchior, Guido. 2017. Sensitivity has Multiple Heterogeneity Problems: a Reply to Wallbridge (2017) .” Philosophia 45(4): 1741–1747, doi:10.1007/s11406-017-9873-5.
      Melchior, Guido. 2019. Knowing and Checking: An Epistemological Investigation. New York: Routledge, doi:10.1007/s12136-022-00540-1.
      Melchior, Guido. 2020. Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology.” Oxford Bibliographies Online, doi:10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0404.
      Melchior, Guido. 2021. A Modal Theory of Discrimination.” Synthese 198(11): 10661–10684, doi:10.1007/s11229-020-02747-4.
      Menzies, Peter. 2014. Counterfactual Theories of Causation.” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, California: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language; Information, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/causation-counterfactual/.
      Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
      Pritchard, Duncan. 2012. In Defence of Modest Anti-Luck Epistemology.” in The Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology, edited by Kelly Becker and Tim Black, pp. 173–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511783630.014.
      Roush, Sherrilyn. 2005. Tracking Truth. Knowledge, Evidence, and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/0199274738.001.0001.
      Salerno, Joseph [Joe]. 2010. Truth Tracking and the Problem of Reflective Knowledge.” in Knowledge and Skepticism, edited by Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O’Rourke, and Harry S. Silverstein, pp. 73–84. Topics in Contemporary Philosophy n. 5. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262014083.003.0004.
      Sosa, Ernest. 1999. How to Defeat Opposition to Moore.” in Philosophical Perspectives 13: Epistemology, edited by James E. Tomberlin, pp. 141–153. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, doi:10.1111/0029-4624.33.s13.7.
      Starr, William B. 2019. Counterfactuals.” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, California: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language; Information, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/counterfactuals/.
      Vogel, Jonathan. 1987. Tracking, Closure, and Inductive Knowledge.” in The Possibility of Knowledge. Nozick and His Critics, edited by Steven Luper, pp. 197–217. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield. Published under the name “Luper-Foy”.
      Vogel, Jonathan. 1999. The New Relevant Alternatives Theory.” in Philosophical Perspectives 13: Epistemology, edited by James E. Tomberlin, pp. 155–180. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, doi:10.1111/0029-4624.33.s13.8.
      Vogel, Jonathan. 2000. Reliabilism Leveled .” The Journal of Philosophy 97(11): 602–623, doi:10.2307/2678454.
      Wallbridge, Kevin. 2017. Sensitivity hasn’t Got a Heterogeneity Problem: a Reply to Melchior (2015).” Philosophia 45(2): 835–841, doi:10.1007/s11406-016-9782-z.
      Wallbridge, Kevin. 2018. Sensitivity, Induction, and Miracles.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96(1): 118–126, doi:10.1080/00048402.2017.1328697.
      Walters, Lee. 2016. Possible World Semantics and True-True Counterfactuals.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97(3): 332–346, doi:10.1111/papq.12067.
      Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/019925656X.001.0001.
      Zalabardo, José L. 2016. Reflective Knowledge and the Nature of Truth.” Disputatio 8(43): 147–171, doi:10.2478/disp-2016-0009.

    Further References

      Lewis, David. 2001. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Republication of Lewis (1973).
      Sosa, Ernest and Steup, Matthias, eds. 2005. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. 1st ed. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy n. 3. Boston, Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishers. Second edition: Steup, Turri and Sosa (2014).
      Steup, Matthias, Turri, John and Sosa, Ernest, eds. 2014. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. 2nd ed. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy n. 3. Malden, Massachusetts: Wiley-Blackwell. First edition: Sosa and Steup (2005), doi:10.1002/9781394260744.