Beta version. This is a page made for testing purposes. For the official version of the article, please visit to OJS webpage at https://dialectica.philosophie.ch/.
Many philosophers regard the persistence of philosophical
disputes as symptomatic of overly ambitious, ill-founded
intellectual projects. There are indeed strong reasons to
believe that persistent disputes in philosophy (and more
generally in the discourse at large) are pointless. We call this
the pessimistic view of the nature of philosophical disputes. In
order to respond to the pessimistic view, we articulate the
supporting reasons and provide a precise formulation in terms of
the idea that the best explanation of persistent disputes
entails that they are pointless. We then show how to answer the
pessimistic argument. Taking a well-known mathematical
controversy as our paradigm example, we argue that some
persistent disputes reflect substantive disagreements at the
“meta-analytic” level, i.e., disagreements about the best way,
among quite different candidates, to understand the topic at
issue, and the best associated cluster of analytic truths one
should accept concerning it. Moreover, our concrete example
shows that such meta-analytic disagreements can, in principle,
be settled and yield a genuine theoretical (as opposed to merely
pragmatic) breakthroughs. We conclude optimistically that
persistent disputes can be an important means of fostering
epistemic progress.
It is commonplace to observe that people tend to disagree and argue
about a multitude of issues, from the most trivial to the most
sophisticated. Some disputes last but briefly, others endure for more
significant lengths of time (sometimes for decades or even, arguably,
for centuries). The history of philosophy is replete with disputes of
the latter, long-lasting kind; or, as we call them, “persistent”
disputes. To take a few illustrative examples, consider the
nominalism-realism debate, the “free will” debate, or the mind-body
problem. The persistence of philosophical disputes has often been taken
as symptomatic of over-ambitious and wrongheaded intellectual projects;
the very ubiquity of such disputes has been used as an argument for the
need for an extensive overhaul of the field.1 For
instance, Descartes dismissed both the philosophy and the science of his
predecessors as dubious and ultimately ill-grounded, “seeing that it has
been cultivated for many centuries by the best minds that have ever
lived, and that nevertheless no single thing is to be found in it which
is not subject of dispute.” Ironically, Locke subsequently accused
Cartesians of breeding “disputes […] never coming to any clear
Resolution […] proper to only continue and increase their Doubts, and to
confirm them at last in a perfect Skepticism” (Locke 1975, 31).2 In
his autobiography, Hume explained that he was struck very early by the
fact that “Philosophy […] contain[s] little more than endless Disputes,
even in the most fundamental Articles.”3
Kant began his first critique with a gloom-ridden reflection on the fact
that metaphysics is nothing but “a battle-field of endless
controversies.” In the 20th century, Wittgenstein and Schlick, among
others, expressed a similar verdict. “Two thousand years of experience,
argues Schlick, seem to teach that efforts to put an end to the chaos of
systems and to change the fate of philosophy can no longer be taken
seriously” (Schlick
1930, 53–54). Wittgenstein famously construed this chaos as a
series of “endless misunderstandings.”4
Yet these philosophers disagreed both on the exact diagnosis and on
the best treatment of persistent disputes. While Descartes thought that
philosophy needed a constructive reestablishment that would put an end
to its persistent disputes by answering the questions that had given
rise to them, other philosophers thought that the revisions needed would
turn out to be destructive rather than constructive, appearing to defuse
persistent disputes yet without answering the questions that had given
rise to them. While Rationalists such as Descartes took it that
persistent philosophical disputes could be solved in principle, if only
the proper rational steps were taken, Empiricists and Kantians believed
that they could only be “dissolved.” For these latter philosophers, the
very fact that the enduring disputes had lasted for such a long time
meant that they could not be solved at all (thus the endless
characterization), and that it was simply pointless for the contending
parties to continue to argue over the disputed
matters. In what follows, we shall call “pessimistic” the claim that
persistent disputes are always pointless and “optimistic” the claim that
they are not always so. We shall come back to the question of why
Rationalists, but not Empiricists, tend to be optimistic about
persistent disputes.Despite its impressive philosophical pedigree and
the admittedly strong intuition it embodies, the pessimistic stance on
persistent disputes has seldom been adequately defended. Contemporary
researchers do often appeal explicitly to pessimistic intuitions,
usually in order to dissolve some perennial disputes (in
metaphysics, think of Hirsch 2016, 138; 2009, 241; in epistemology, of
Alston 2005, 21–23; in metaphilosophy, of van Inwagen 2017, 129–131; or
Stoljar 2017).5 However, they hardly try to justify
or deepen that intuition. To our knowledge, there is no direct argument
in the literature purporting to show that, in philosophy or elsewhere,
persistent disputes must be pointless in virtue of their very
persistence. Moreover, no one has explicitly pointed out what is
supposed to be wrong with the fact that a dispute persists for a long
time. This paper aims at filling this lacuna while delineating the
optimistic defense of persistent disputes.
After having defined disputes in section 1 and their persistence in section 2, we survey in section 3 the different ways in which a dispute may be
said to be pointless. We then put forward in section 4 what we take to be the strongest pessimistic
challenge to the optimistic claim that persistent disputes may in fact
have a point. The challenge relies, as we shall see, on the fact that
when a dispute persists for a long time, the best explanation for its
persistence seems to render it pointless. In section 5, we consider a real-world example of a
persistent dispute that has turned out demonstrably to have a point: the
“Functions Controversy.” Drawing on this example, we argue that some
persistent disputes do have a point, and that their point is
meta-analytic, implicitly concerning the best way, among quite different
candidates, of understanding the terms and objects at issue. We show
that such meta-analytic disputes can be settled and yield genuine
theoretical (as opposed to merely pragmatic) progress.
The topic of disagreement has recently come to the fore of the
philosophical agenda, yielding a multiplicity of debates about faultless
disagreements, peer disagreements, deep disagreements, philosophical
disagreements, and the a priori, conceptual engineering and
metalinguistic negotiations. The question of persistent disputes, as we
shall see, cuts across a variety of debates. It is therefore difficult
(if not impossible) to do full justice to the precise ways in which
these varied approaches interact. In the penultimate section 7, however, we connect our optimistic defense
of persistent disputes to some of these recent debates and argue that it
can prove fruitful for our understanding of the importance of
metalinguistic negotiations and related phenomena in science and
philosophy.
1 Disputes
At first approximation, a dispute over a sentence \(q\) is a situation in which different parties
seem to disagree about \(q\):
while Pro asserts \(q\)’s truth, Con
denies it,6
argue against each other in order to find out which one is
correct, and which one is incorrect.
Note that there are countless ways in which one might object to this
first approximation, going on consequently to build in complex and
precise detail by way of refinement and exactitude. For our present
purposes, however, a brief characterization should suffice.
Parties.
The parties involved in a dispute might be
single individuals, or collectively, they might form groups. Moreover,
the weight or preponderance of the argument on each side might well be
asymmetric. Consider, for example, the dispute over whether the earth is
flat, opposing (in the present day) a negligibly small number of
flat-earthers to virtually everyone else. Or, to take a limit case,
think about the disputes opposing some delusional patients to their
doctors and families (see Hohwy and
Rosenberg 2005; Bayne and Pacherie 2004 for a couple of relevant case
reports).
Aims.
We assume in this paper that the primary
aim of a dispute is to find out who is right or wrong, that
is, whether Pro’s assertion is true, and Con’s is false or the opposite.
Some might object that the aim of a dispute should be construed in terms
of knowledge, or of some other norm of assertion, rather than truth
(see e.g.,
Williamson 2000). This point is well taken. Because it will make
things simpler, however, and because we believe it does not affect the
main thrust of our arguments, we will neglect alternative,
knowledge-based, views of the primary aim of
disputes.
Be that as it may, a dispute might be quite useful even when it does
not fulfil its primary aim. Pursuing it might, for
example, allow the disputants to attain other valuable cognitive goals,
such as finding out that it is impossible to reach the primary aim of the dispute, or that they need further
evidence, or again that this dispute is connected in surprising ways to
other classical disputes, and so on. In the case of collective or
group-based disagreements, the dispute might allow a select few
individuals to realize whether or not they are correct, even in the
absence of a collective forming of opinion. In such cases, we might say
that the dispute has fulfilled some of its secondary aims, and that it is accordingly
interesting, even if it has no point. Finally, when neither its
primary aim nor its secondary
aims can be reached, a dispute might still serve what we might call
adventitious aims: aims that are not
directly related to epistemic values. Participating in a philosophical
dispute to which one has skillfully and adeptly devoted time and effort,
for example, might help one keep one’s job as a philosopher and pay
one’s rent on time.
2 Persistence
What about persistent disputes, one might ask? “Persistent”
is a rather vague and context-sensitive word. In order to make explicit
what we mean by it, we need to be clear as to the role we assign to the
notion of persistent disputes. This notion is epistemologically useful
and significant, we believe, because the persistence of a dispute casts
a doubt on its having a point. For the doubt to arise, two things are
necessary. First, a persistent dispute must have existed long enough to
allow all participating parties to share their
evidence, extensively argue, and thoroughly assess the arguments put
forward. Although this might depend on the pace of exchanges and on the
number of people involved, it might be surmised that several decades
should suffice for the process to be completed. However, this condition
is neither precise, nor sufficient, for constraining the analysis. To
see why, suppose that new and important experimental results for and
against \(q\) reliably emerge over a
short period of time (say, every year), and that as a result, a couple
of antagonistic scientists contend over \(q\) for decades. The very long time they
have spent arguing would not be epistemically challenging, or not quite
as much as it would have been, had the relevant empirical evidence
remained constant all along. It would indeed be easily explained by the
continuous discovery of new empirical data, contributing to each new
iteration of their argument. Accordingly, if we do not want to deprive
the category of persistent disputes of much of its epistemological
usefulness and significance, we should say that a dispute over \(q\) is persistent only if, while the
relevant available empirical evidence did not significantly change, it
has lasted long enough to allow all parties to
share their evidence, extensively argue, and thoroughly assess the
arguments put forward. Conversely, we count as persistent a dispute
satisfying this condition. The examples from the history of philosophy
given above do not all qualify as persistent disputes in this sense, as
for some of them (most notably, the “free will” debate), the relevant
empirical evidence has in fact significantly changed over the centuries.
But one thing the debates we adverted to should have in common is that
they all involve a series of persistent disputes in our given
sense. Thus, one might say that both the discovery of classical
mechanics and the discovery of quantum mechanics ended a form of
persistent dispute over free will and, at the same time, gave rise to a
new variant. Similarly, when Thomas Young made his two-slit experiment,
one arguably persistent dispute over the nature of light (wave or
particle) ended, and another one took its place.
3 Varieties of Pointless
Disputes
3.1 What Is a Pointless
Dispute?
Throwing a rock at the sky is pointless if it is aimed at knocking
the moon off orbit or at causing rainfall in the Sahara. It is not
pointless if it is part of a game or play. More generally, an action has
a point if and only if, given one’s capacities and the laws of nature,
it allows one to reach the aim we assign to it. A dispute is a kind of
action too, albeit a collective action. And just like throwing a rock,
it will have a point if and only if it permits the disputants to achieve
the aim of the dispute. As we have seen, disputes can be assigned many
aims. Previously, we distinguished the primary aim
of a dispute (finding out who is right and who is wrong) from its secondary aims (such as finding out whether the primary aim can be attained) and adventitious aims (such as keeping one’s job as a
philosopher). No one would be tempted to say that a dispute has a point
only because it allows one to reach some of its adventitious aims. The matter is less
straightforward when it comes to secondary aims.
There is, in any case, an interesting category of disputes that are
pointless in the sense that, given their epistemological profile,
taking part in these disputes cannot allow the disputants to reach the
primary goal of these disputes, that is, cannot allow them to find out
who is right and who is wrong about\(q\). By the “epistemological profile” of a
dispute, we mean not only the rationality of the parties, broadly understood (that is, their
epistemic virtues and capacities, and the various epistemic vices,
motivational influences, and cognitive biases that might hinder the
exercise of the former), but also the way rationality itself (in terms
of capacities, virtues, biases, and influences) evolves over time. We
should also include in the epistemological profile of a dispute the
distribution of the relevant available evidence and its relation to both
parties (i.e., how easily accessible it is to
both) and other relevant epistemological factors. In what follows, we
focus on disputes that are pointless in this primary sense. Importantly,
if a dispute is pointless (in that sense), the fact that the parties want to find out who is right and who is
wrong gives them no practical reason to keep arguing against each other.
If that is the only thing they are hoping to achieve, then the debate is
indeed terminally devoid of point, and the disputants would be better
off engaged in other pursuits.
3.2 A Typology of Pointless
Disputes
It is possible to distinguish four types of pointless disputes.
Notice that appearances notwithstanding, opposing parties engaged in a dispute might in fact both be
right. In such a case, we should say that the dispute is not
genuine. If a dispute is not genuine, then neither of the
disputants is wrong; it is accordingly impossible to find out which of
the two is wrong and a fortiori to settle the issue by arguing
antagonistically. Non-genuine disputes are, therefore, manifestly
pointless. There are, however, two different ways for a dispute to be
non-genuine, as we shall now explain.
Verbal disputes.
Typically, a non-genuine dispute is one in which both partiesdo not genuinely disagree. Yet,
one might ask, how can two speakers fail to disagree if one asserts that
\(q\) is true, while the other denies
it? Such an eventuality might easily obtain if the speakers
misunderstand each other, for example, if \(q\) contains ambiguous terms, and the
disputants are linguistically at odds over the various intended
contents. In such a case, it turns out that if there is disagreement at
all, it is about how to use words and their possible meanings, and not
matters of deeper substance. Thus, the apparent dispute is, contrary to
first impressions, merely verbal.7 For instance, it is sometimes
claimed that in matters of taste, disputes are verbal because what “tasty” means is tantamount to
“tasty for the speaker who utters it,” and will, on this analysis, mean
different things as uttered by different speakers. The claim that
metaphysical disputes are verbal corresponds to
a form of metaphysical pluralism. Carnap (1950) seems to have held such a
view about ontology.8Hirsch (2009) has recently revived
that view, arguing that many (but not all) metaphysical disputes are verbal.
Relativist disputes.
There are moreover some non-genuine disputes in which the disputing
parties nevertheless genuinely do disagree. That
is to say, there is no linguistic misunderstanding of the type above,
and yet, intuitively at least, both parties
really do put forward conflicting proposal. A similar conundrum arises:
how can two people, who are said to genuinely disagree with each other,
nevertheless both be correct? The answer is that such a predicament
might occur if the truth of the disputed sentence is relative to certain parameters, be they
moral standards or standards of taste, theoretical frameworks or
paradigms, and similar. Goodman (1978) argues that even when
they are genuinely conflicting and not ambiguous, a sentence \(q\) and its negation can be both correct
because they are not correct in or relative to
the same “world.” Goodman calls his view radical relativism, and his
relativism is indeed radical in the sense that it is universal. More
recently, some philosophers have advocated circumscribed forms of
relativism (see
MacFarlane 2014). Some have argued that disputes about taste are
not usually verbal because adversaries in
matters of taste do not talk past each other; when I say that spinach is
tasty and you deny it, our speech acts bear on the same proposition, and
our disagreement is tangibly real. Such a disagreement, it has been
claimed, might nevertheless be faultless (in the relevant sense that
permits both of us to be right) if truth about matters of taste is made
relative to latent standards of assessment.
Goodman (1978)
has held that metaphysical disputes are relativist and endorsed metaphysical relativism. As
we understand him, Gallie (1956) argues that many
disputes in the political and social domain are “endless,” because they
are relativist. Williams (2011, vii–x) seems to
hold a similar view (which he calls “non-objectivism”) regarding many
moral disputes.
Empty disputes.
Genuine disputes are disputes in which at least one party is
not right about \(q\). Yet
these types of debates might be pointless too. Starkly, this will obtain
when neither party happens to be correct about the matter at issue. In
such a case, the primary aim of the
dispute—finding out which one of the two parties
is right and which is wrong—will as before be impossible to achieve. One
might say by way of a stipulative definition that when both opponents
are not right, their dispute is empty.
Trivially, if the disputed sentence \(q\) is meaningless, the dispute over \(q\) is empty. In
such a case, it is a moot point whether the parties do in fact disagree.9
Expressivists about taste might thus argue that “spinach is tasty” or
“‘spinach is tasty’ is true” are merely expressions of feelings which
are neither true nor false and that disputes about such matters are
always empty. In metaphysics, the claim that
disputes are pointless because they are empty
has been maintained by the Logical Empiricists. It expresses a form of
metaphysical anti-realism (Carnap 1931). Thomasson (2009) and Yablo (2009) argue that
some metaphysical disputes might indeed be empty.
Empty disputes constitute a central case of
the category of pointless genuine disputes. We now come to a third.
Inscrutable disputes.
In order to have a point, a dispute must be genuine and non-empty. Let us call “substantive” a dispute in which
one party is right while the other party is not. Not all substantive
disputes have a point. A substantive dispute will indeed be pointless if
it is impossible for the parties to come to an
agreement through rational exchange, that is, if the epistemic reasons
justifying the assertion or the denial of \(q\) are inaccessible to one of the parties. Note that the impossibility and
inaccessibility at stake in this context are epistemological. They
depend on what we have called the epistemological profile of the
dispute, and in particular on the rationality of the disputants. We call
those disputes whose epistemological profile makes it impossible to
convince by dint of reasons the error-committing party, inscrutable disputes. The claim that traditional
metaphysical disputes are pointless because they are inscrutable expresses a form of metaphysical
skepticism. This Humean or Kantian view has contemporary advocates.
Kriegel
(2013) puts forward an argument to the effect that they are
always inscrutable. Bennett (2009) claims that some of
them are.
Verbal, relativist,
empty, and inscrutable
disputes are subcategories of pointless debate. Conversely, if a dispute
is neither verbal nor relativist, empty or inscrutable, it is a substantive dispute in which,
given their cognitive capacities, the disputants can, in principle, come
to an agreement over \(q\) by means of
argument and rational persuasion. It will accordingly be a dispute that
has a point. Verbal, relativist, empty, and inscrutable disputes thus nicely partition the
field of pointless disputes (see 1).
Note that there is an interesting contrast between verbal, relativist, and empty disputes, on the one hand, and inscrutable disputes, on the other. Whereas the
first three types are pointless for a semantic or an ontological reason,
the last type is pointless for an epistemic reason. Importantly, as we
have emphasized, a dispute might be pointless but still interesting and,
accordingly, worth having. Bennett (2009) claims that this has
been the case of some ontological disputes that are inscrutable, and Sosa (2010, 281) argues that this is
the case of many philosophical disputes that are verbal.
4 The Pessimistic Challenge to
Persistent Disputes
Our general discussion of the futility of disputes is directly
relevant to persistent disputes, which may turn out to be
pointless in precisely four different ways, on the present analysis:
they may be verbal, relativist, empty, or inscrutable. Our question is now the following: Is
there something in the persistence of a dispute that makes it likely to
fall into one of these categories? It may be assumed that some
persistent disputes are pointless, but why should the very persistence
of a dispute always make it pointless? Since we are envisaging an
internal connection between persistence and pointlessness, we need to
examine general arguments for the pointlessness of persistent
disputes. We shall see, however, that these general arguments can also
be applied on a case-by-case basis, yielding more cogent conclusions for
some persistent disputes, as opposed to others.
There is an obvious inductive argument which infers endlessness from
persistence: if a dispute has existed for a very long time without
having been settled successfully, it will never be. When Empiricists or
Kantians say that metaphysical disputes are endless, they seem
to appeal implicitly to an argument of this kind. The weakness of the
inductive argument is easy to see once the latter is made explicit. For
instance, a similar argument would have concluded twenty years ago that
the perennial search for a demonstration of Fermat’s last theorem was
pointless, which we know is obviously false.10
More significantly, the inductive argument fails to distinguish
between persistent disputes and persistent questions.
When a dispute exists for a very long time, the intuitive worry is not
so much that a complicated question fails of an answer (persistent
questions are legion in mathematics and natural sciences, and few would
claim that their persistence means that they are pointless). The
intuitive worry is rather that, despite their common knowledge of
the unsettled issues, the parties do not
relinquish their dispute and continue to hold and argue for (apparently)
dissenting views. In a genuine persistent dispute, one of the parties does not know that she is not right, and
that she does not know the answer to the question. But this is not so,
in general, with a persistent question (think again of the many
conjectures and open problems in mathematics and physics which do not
yield persistent disputes). Unlike persistent questions, persistent
disputes involve a form of reflective opacity. Accordingly,
they seem much more worrying from an epistemological point of view than
mere persistent questions.11
This intuitive worry forms the basis of a serious philosophical
challenge, a challenge that is abductive rather than inductive. The
challenge is to explain the persistence of a given dispute without
assuming that it is pointless. What might account for the fact that parties persist in disputing a sentence’s truth if
their dispute is not, in one way or another, pointless? Below, we will
introduce two important and connected problems that the theorist we have
characterized as optimist must face in order to answer this
challenge. The first one is, roughly, that if a dispute which has a
point persists, both parties should become
competent enough to settle it after a reasonable time. This dispute
should not, accordingly, be persistent. This is the competence
problem. The second one, which we call the problem of apt a
priori disagreement, can be stated thus: when a dispute persists
and involves sufficiently rational subjects who can share the relevant
empirical evidence, it reflects a persisting a priori
disagreement among rational subjects whose judgments are both apt. But
it is hard to see how such a thing could be possible. Taken together,
these two problems suggest that the challenge cannot be met and that
persistent disputes are pointless.
4.1 The Competence Problem
How can a dispute persist if it is not pointless? A successful
explanation should first grant that the dispute is substantive: one
party must be wrong and the other right; otherwise, the dispute would be
merely verbal, relativist, or empty, and
hence pointless. It should accordingly explain the persistence of the
dispute in epistemological terms, invoking a bad epistemological profile
of the dispute. The epistemological profile must not be too bad,
however; that is to say, it must not be incorrigibly bad, for otherwise
the dispute would be inscrutable and pointless.
In other words, the parties should be competent
enough to settle the dispute, but their performance should be impeded by
some epistemological obstacles liable to be overcome, albeit extremely
slowly.
Let us see how this might happen by singling out the epistemological
obstacles that might plausibly explain persistent disagreements—call
these persistent disagreement factors12—and see whether they can explain a
persistent dispute. Persistent disagreement factors all hinge on an
asymmetry in the distribution of certain epistemic features that need to
be overcome.
Asymmetric access to empirical evidence. Rational agents do
not, as a rule, have equal access to all available empirical evidence
relevant to a given question. This fact explains many of our persistent
disagreements. For instance, I believe that the male rather than the
female of the seahorse species carries eggs because I recall coming
across this information in a book on marine life roughly thirty years
ago. My partner believes the opposite because it seems to him less
implausible as a scientific hypothesis. We have disagreed all this time
(to be frank, we never much talked about it).
Similarly, I can disagree with my neighbor about the claim that
vaccines are on the whole more dangerous than the disease against which
they offer immunity, at least in part because I happen to have access to
far more reliable scientific sources than he does and because my
sources, but not his, inform my opinion correctly in view of the
relevant facts. Consequently, the disagreement can rage on unabated for
a considerable period.
Some theists likewise explain their disagreement with atheists, as
well as with advocates of rival religions, by claiming that
they have experienced the presence of (their version of) God
(among
philosophers, see, among others, the influential accounts of Plantinga
2000; Alston 1991).
Differences in rationality. Psychologists have shown that we
are almost without exception affected by cognitive biases and that,
consequently, different thinkers display different cognitive “styles.”
They have also shown that our motivations can significantly affect our
beliefs and their entrenchment. It is safe to suppose that cognitive and
motivational biases can account for a range of persistent
disagreements.
Take the following puzzle, a paradigm case for attracting
disagreement. Suppose Linda is 31 years old,
single, outspoken, and very bright. She majored in philosophy. As a
student, she was deeply concerned with issues of discrimination and
social justice, and also participated in anti-nuclear demonstrations.
Which is more probable? That Linda is a bank
teller, or that Linda is a bank teller and is
active in the feminist movement? Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky
(1982) have argued convincingly that many people wrongly believe
that the second option is the more probable because they use a
misleading representativeness heuristic to assess probabilities.
Moreover, it has been observed that psychological factors can affect
real-life persistent philosophical disagreements. Enoch (2011, 192–195) has argued that
many moral disagreements are partly grounded on the distorting effects
of self-interest. As an illustration, he mentions the view advocated by
Peter Singer and Peter Unger to the effect that unless we give almost
all our money to famine relief, we are nearly as morally condemnable as
murderers. As he says, “refusing to see the (purported) truth of
Singer’s and Unger’s claims thus has tremendous psychological payoffs”
(Enoch 2011,
193).
Feltz and
Cokely (2013) have likewise argued that some “persistent
philosophical disagreements” are predicted by individual differences, in
particular by personality traits, which determine certain cognitive
biases. They show, for instance, that extroverts tend to endorse the
compatibility of free will and determinism.
Different epistemic paths and starting points. Finally, some
persistent disagreements can be explained by factors that do not
directly depend on differences in rationality or access to the relevant
empirical evidence, but only on what we might call the
topography of the disagreement. That is, on the different
starting points, and on the different paths taken in the course of a
disagreement. The idea is to compare the evolution of someone’s opinion
on a given topic to climbing a mountain. Even if two people are aiming
at the same terminus (by analogy, truth), and even if they are in a
perfect physical condition (by analogy, even if they are perfectly
rational and have common access to the relevant empirical evidence),
they might end up in different places simply because they had different
starting points, took different paths thereafter, and because the
landscape itself is full of pitfalls.13
Arguably, the most notable pitfalls are what philosophers call
vicious epistemic circles. Often, such circles successfully
entrap ordinary subjects, altering the form of their beliefs and
creating the conditions for long-standing divergence of opinion. Thus,
the prevalence of conspiracy theories in some social contexts has been
explained in terms of the fact that some people do not trust the
accredited experts because they do not trust the institutions bestowing
credentials upon them. But they do not trust the institutions
accrediting the latter because they believe in conspiracy theories.
Conspiracy theorists are trapped in a vicious epistemic circle. Basham (2001, 270ff)
has argued that, as a result, we are not in general in a position to
find out whether a claim of conspiracy is correct. We cannot but assume
a prior answer to the core question of how conspiracy-prone our society
is, in order to derive a well-justified position on the issue (Basham 2001, 274).
If Basham’s view is correct, those who start by trusting institutions
end up rejecting conspiracy theories, and those who distrust them are
bound to adopt conspiracy theories. Vicious epistemic circles have also
been invoked to explain the fixity of delusional beliefs (Hohwy and
Rosenberg 2005; Bayne and Pacherie 2004) and the persistent
disagreement between for-vaccine and anti-vaccine factions, and
flat-earthers and their opponents (see, e.g., Levy’s 2019
account of scientific denialism; and Nguyen’s 2020 account of echo
chambers).
Note that these disagreement factors can explain persistent
disagreements. Can they explain persistent disputes,
and persistent disputes that have a point, and are hence substantive and
“scrutable”? In a dispute (as opposed to in a mere disagreement) the parties argue to correct and convince each other.14 In a scrutable dispute, moreover,
the epistemological profile must be good enough to allow the parties ultimately to settle the dispute by means
of rational argument. The parties must be
sufficiently rational (the cognitive biases and the motivational
influences on beliefs affecting them must be benign and corrigible),
vicious circles must be eschewed, and the relevant available evidence
must be equally accessible to both. In such a scrutable dispute, time
will accordingly have a beneficial effect. It will progressively cancel
not only performance errors, but also the impact of differences in
rationality (due, for example, in cognitive biases and motivational
influences) as well as the asymmetries in the access to the empirical
evidence. For a scrutable dispute to persist, this beneficial effect of
time must be real, but extremely slow. The gist of the competence
argument is that in most cases, such a very slow effect is simply
implausible: either the disputants are competent enough to settle the
dispute, and it should be settled in a reasonable amount of time, or
they are not competent, and the dispute is pointless.
Let us see how this works on the above examples. It is reasonable to
suppose that the disagreement about seahorses’ eggs and the disagreement
about probabilities in the Linda example will
not yield anything like a persistent dispute, or at least not one that
is scrutable. If the dispute is scrutable, both parties have the capacity to acknowledge without
further ado the decisive evidence to the effect that male seahorses
carry eggs or that it is more likely that Linda
is a bank teller rather than a bank teller and something else. It is
hard to see what could prevent them, then, to quickly come to an
agreement.
In the theistic example, on the other hand, it seems that the
disagreement could indeed yield a persistent dispute, but it is dubious
that the asymmetries in the access to the relevant empirical evidence
can be redressed by means of simple debate. As James (1902, 371) emphasized, religious
experiences are usually very difficult to communicate. They seem to
provide what is sometimes called subjective, private or first-person
evidence (Schellenberg 2007, ch. viii).
Accordingly, if the religious disagreement case yields a persistent
dispute, this is likely to be merely of the pointless kind.
The moral disagreement case, the free will case, and the anti-vaccine
case are less straightforward to analyze. Historically, disagreements of
their type have given rise to genuine disputes, both at the factional
(group) level and at the level of individual thinkers. There are
reasons, however, to believe that such group-level disputes are
pointless. Take the moral disagreement, for example, and suppose, for
the sake of the argument, that Singer and Unger are right and that their
opponents are simply self-deceived. For the dispute to have a point, it
must be possible, through rational exchange, to correct the distorting
influence of their self-interest on their beliefs and have them change
their mind. But even if we could do that, it would not suffice to settle
the debate, as there would always be new, self-deceived comers joining
the ranks of Singer’s and Unger’s opponents who have not yet benefited
from the virtues of rational redress. The ensuing dispute would arguably
be pointless. A similar analysis might deal with the anti-vaccine and
the free will cases. The problem in such cases is that new members of
one group seem to be selected by their epistemic limitations (more
precisely, by how they fare on some disagreement factor), which prevents
the dispute from being settled.
The competence challenge is not a knockdown objection against
persistent disputes that have a point. Nothing prevents, theoretically
at least, the possibility that a dispute exists which is shaped by
cognitive biases, asymmetries in the access to evidence, or differences
in starting points and epistemic circles that can be overcome, albeit
extremely slowly. The competence challenge can, however, yield a schema
of abductive arguments that should be applied on a case-by-case basis,
as we have illustrated above. For a given persistent dispute, depending
on the precise details of the case, the strategy of appealing to the
argument schema implies that the best explanation of why such a dispute
persists makes it pointless. It is in fact arguable that many
pessimistic views about the debates in metaphysics and elsewhere stem
implicitly from the idea that in these cases of interest, disagreement
factors are set at rest once by one, making persistence mysterious.
There is moreover a broad category of cases to which the competence
challenge can be applied directly, as opposed to on a case-by-case
basis, characteristic of our argument schema strategy. It is the
category of disputes in which differences in rationality are
sufficiently easy to overcome, the epistemic circles sufficiently easy
to escape, the starting points sufficiently close, the relevant
available evidence sufficiently easy to access or share, and the
epistemic profile of the dispute, more broadly, sufficiently auspicious.
Call such disputes virtuous disputes. In such cases, the
disagreement factors we discussed, which might explain the dispute
without making it pointless, will most likely be cancelled after a short
period of rational exchanges (perhaps in the space of a couple of
years). Virtuous disputes, it should be emphasized, need not have a
point. Virtuous disputes are such, however, that their epistemic profile
seems incapable of explaining their persistence without making them
pointless. But it is hard to see what else could explain their
persistence; accordingly, the argument concludes, they will only persist
because they are pointless, i.e., because they are verbal, relative or empty.
The point raised above is interesting, since many disputes seem at
least prima facie virtuous, and some of these seem persistent too. Think
of disputes among researchers on such topics as mereological composition
in ontology, or fundamental axioms in mathematics (for example, disputes
about the truth of the continuum hypothesis). Or consider, in biology,
the disputes over the choice of a classification system based on
phylogeny vs. interbreeding (LaPorte 2004, 70–76); or, in
cognitive neuroscience, the dispute over the neural correlates of visual
consciousness; or, in cosmology, disputes over the status of
multiverses. Many people engage in these disputes with the hope of
settling them in a reasonable time, and they seem to believe that these
disputes are virtuous (the case of ontological debates is perhaps moot).
There is no question that self-interest sometimes plays a role in them,
some researchers being motivated, for example, by the perspective of
promotions and social recognition. It is, however, at least prima facie
plausible that such motivational influence and other aspects of the
epistemic profile cannot explain the persistence of these disputes. At
least this is what many researchers engaged in these disputes seem to
believe.
In short, the competence challenge enjoins us to find an explanation
why some disputes stubbornly persist, which does not entail
pointlessness. In many cases, it is difficult to understand how the
dispute may persist for protracted periods of time without being
pointless, since, as we have outlined, if the dispute has a point, the
participating parties must be sufficiently
competent to settle it, and the passage of time must bring with it
adequate and timely redress. This then is the Competence
Problem. It might be possible to meet this challenge for some forms
of persistent debates. It is difficult, however, to see how this might
proceed, especially in the case of virtuous disputes.
4.2 The Problem of Apt A Priori
Disagreements
The Competence Problem is related to a second cognate
difficulty, namely the Problem of Apt A Priori Disagreements.
Roughly sketched, this says that (i) when a virtuous dispute is
persistent, it becomes a priori; (ii) however, given that the disputants
involved in a virtuous dispute are equally competent to assess a priori
claims, it is very hard to see what could explain the persistence of
their dispute. We tackle these two premises in turn.
Since the disputants engaged in a persistent virtuous dispute are
said to gain quick and easy access to a shared empirical body of
relevant evidence, one might suppose that their disagreement
would at some early point become independent of relevant empirical
evidence. Since other pieces of empirical evidence are, ex hypothesis,
not relevant to this dispute, the disagreement is also independent of
these latter. Overall, the dispute thus becomes independent of
all empirical evidence, relevant as well as irrelevant, and,
accordingly, a priori.
If the virtuous dispute over the sentence \(q\) is not pointless, the persistent
disagreement will in fact be grounded on a (more or less explicit)
disagreement over a more fundamental sentence \(q\*\) , to the effect that the available
empirical evidence provides decisive reasons for \(q\). The sentence \(q\*\) will be a priori not only because the
difference in attitudes toward it (namely, one party believes that \(q\*\) is true, the other one that it is
false) is not grounded on a difference in empirical evidence, but also
because, if the parties were to settle the
dispute, their correct attitude toward \(q\*\) would not be similarly grounded
either.
There are classical, Platonic, and Kantian arguments to the effect
that fundamental disagreements in metaphysics and ethics hinge on a
priori claims.15 Our argument is much simpler and
much more modest than these. First, our argument relies on a dialectical
and quasi-operational conception of the a priori (expressed by the
necessary condition that, to the effect that a disagreement which does
not depend on problems of rationality or on empirical evidence, must be
a priori) that remains neutral on the cognitive mechanisms implied.16 Moreover, our argument only targets
disputes (not just disagreements) with a point, and only those,
moreover, that are both persistent and virtuous. To reiterate, for a
dispute to have a point, the relevant empirical evidence must be equally
accessible . If the dispute is, moreover, virtuous and persistent, this
equally accessible evidence must quickly become equally accessed in
actual fact. Hence the dispute must quickly become a priori, depending
only on a priori claims.17
Let us illustrate this point with an example. For the last two
decades, neuropsychologists have disagreed about the neural correlates
of visual consciousness; all the while, the accessible relevant
empirical evidence did not change significantly. Roughly, while some
(call them Pro) believe that the neural correlate necessarily involves
frontoparietal networks, others (call them Con) believe that an
activation of primary visual areas in the occiput is sufficient for
visual consciousness.18 Strikingly, they all agree on the
data collected by both camps and on their prima facie relevance to the
debate. While some have characterized this debate (in this and ancillary
areas) as merely verbal(see, for
example, Bayne 2007, 100; Rosenthal 2002, 660; and even more
specifically, Gottlieb 2018), it is arguable that nevertheless
the dispute is substantive, granted that they disagree on the way the
universally accepted common data should be weighed and interpreted, and
that their disagreement is grounded on a priori claims about scientific
methodology and scientific concepts. Pro scientists explicitly suggest,
for example, that consciousness is a priori tied to reportability and
that the only scientifically tractable concept of consciousness is that
of “cognitive access”; while Con scientists argue that consciousness is
not tied a priori to reportability but is still scientifically tractable
(see, for example,
Block’s Block 2007b insightful analysis of this debate).19
It may already seem mysterious that thinkers disagree on an a priori
truth, but when being rational, they are competent enough to find out
that it is indeed true. It gets all the more mysterious when their
disagreement persists despite lively rational exchanges, since we can
safely assume that they correct each other’s performance errors and that
their disagreement does not stem from such errors—it is an apt a priori
disagreement. The problem here is not so much that one of the parties persistently fails to assent to a truth
(\(q\*\) or its negation) that is a
priori even though he is rational enough to do so and does not commit
performance errors. After all, many competent subjects have persistently
failed to see that some complex mathematical claims, such as Fermat’s
theorem or Poincaré’s conjecture, follow from the relevant axioms. We
already know that some a priori questions can persist for
decades or centuries. The problem is rather that one of the parties wrongly and persistently dissents
on the matter of the disputed a priori truth, and that both parties accordingly disagree persistently. In the
case of Fermat’s theorem, Poincare’s conjecture, and many other
classical conjectures, the historical landscape is starkly different—at
least if we attend to the categorical assertions published in
peer-reviewed journals and backed by tentative proofs, as opposed to
hypothetical assertions expressed in conversation and backed by
intuitions. Mathematicians may dissent for a couple of years about
whether a particular complex proof of a given conjecture is correct (the
recent example of the six-hundred-page-long proof of the \(abc\) conjecture is a particularly eloquent
example; cf. Castelvecchi (2020)). When no
convincing proof has been published, they may persistently fail to know
the truth of the matter, and consequently suspend their (considered)
judgments for a long time, but they do not generally disagree
persistently about it.20 The problem of non-pointless but
persistent virtuous disputes is that, being reflectively opaque, they
seem to imply the existence of a kind of deceptive a priori
truths; truths, that is, such that rational enough subjects not only
fail to know them, but also wrongly believe them to be false (not
knowing that they do not know them). We take it that deceptive a priori
truths typically represent a kind of a priori truth whose existence will
be granted by Rationalists, but denied by Empiricists, and that the
challenge of apt a priori disagreements thus goes some way towards
explaining why Rationalists, but not Empiricists, tend to be optimists
about persistent disputes.
Logical Empiricists notably argued that all a priori truths are
analytic and that rational subjects should assent to analytic truths
merely in virtue of understanding them (at least if they do not make any
performance errors). Assuming that two parties
are sufficiently rational, and therefore capable of grasping a prior
truth, there should be no room for disagreement about which a priori
truths are true. Conversely, if rational subjects disagree about an a
priori sentence, it follows that either they understand the disputed
sentence differently and the dispute is verbal,
or they do not really understand it and it is empty.21 Logical Empiricists
must thus reject the existence of the deceptive a priori and
deny that persistent virtuous disputes can have a point.
One preliminary conclusion to draw from our discussion is that a
theorist who believes that some persistent virtuous disputes have a
point is committed to maintaining either that some a priori claims are
synthetic rather than analytic, or else that some analytic
claims are such that understanding them does not suffice to assent to
them.
The first option makes ineliminable use of the notion of the
synthetic a priori. Plausibly, it entails that persistent virtuous
disputes are grounded in a difference in the rational or a priori
evidence accessed by both parties. Such a
difference would be an additional disagreement factor, one that we have
not considered so far but that has the potential, in principle, to
explain persistent virtuous disputes. The second option has an air of
oddity about it. It implies that one could, after decades of reflection,
completely change his mind about an analytic claim he understood very
well all along.22 We believe that neither option is
completely implausible (we are, in fact, quite sympathetic to the
synthetic a priori option). Yet, unless they are fleshed out in more
detail, it seems that both strategies can only rename the problem of
persistent disputes but not resolve it.
We are now able to sum up the pessimistic challenge to persistent
disputes.
First, if persistent disputes have a point, they must involve
disputants that are competent enough to settle the dispute. Yet it is
difficult to see how such disputes may persist for an inordinately long
time since, if they have a point, obstacles hindering the disputants’
performances will be gradually overcome. Indeed, it seems that the
longer a dispute lasts, the less reasons there are to persist.
Second, since parties in a persistent
virtuous dispute swiftly gain access to the same relevant empirical
evidence, their disagreement becomes apt and a priori in due course.
This means that persistent virtuous disputes involve deceptive a priori
truths: a priori truths that sufficiently rational thinkers, who do not
err because of performance errors, reject and unknowingly fail to
know.
We believe that even perfectly virtuous disputes can persist and have
a point; hence, that the pessimistic challenge may be answered—and,
indeed, in a rather mundane way. In order to answer this challenge, one
need not appeal to any dubious form of rational intuition nor posit
cognitive biases, epistemic circles, or asymmetries in the access to the
empirical evidence that can only be overcome at an extremely slow pace.
One need just acknowledge the existence of a common type of dispute,
that we call meta-analytic and that, for reasons we will soon explain,
can be extremely long to settle. Our argumentative strategy will rely on
a real-world example: a well-known persistent mathematical dispute,
which uncontroversially proved to have a point.
5 An Example of Scientific
Persistent Dispute: The Functions Controversy
Persistent disputes are not specific to philosophy and may occur, as
we have seen, within science as well. Showing that a given scientific
controversy that seems persistent really is persistent is far from
trivial, however, as it requires showing that it is not covertly fuelled
by new empirical discoveries (recalling that we have individuated
persistent disputes by the relevant empirical evidence available).
The simplest way to circumvent this problem and to find an
uncontroversial example of a persistent scientific dispute is to opt for
an illustration coming from a purely formal science, such as pure
mathematics. Arguably, in this domain, empirical evidence is irrelevant,
or at least non-decisive, and cannot end a persistent dispute.23
Among disputes that have proved persistent, it is also difficult to
find one that has uncontroversially proved to have a point. Often
enough, prima facie persistent disputes do not appear to be
clearly or definitively settled. Equally, we believe that the domain of
pure mathematics is interesting in virtue of its (approximately)
cumulative character (pace Lakatos 1976). In mathematics,
the fact that a dispute has been deemed settled for a very long time
seems to be a very strong reason to believe that it is indeed
settled.
We understand that using a mathematical example might bring with it
some additional complications. The semantics and ontology of mathematics
are often deemed less straightforward than those of, (say) geology or
biology. We believe that these complications are rather light and
largely outweighed by the advantages of mathematics mentioned in the
preceding paragraph.
The example we have chosen from pure mathematics is the Functions
Controversy. This scientific dispute has the advantage of having been,
without a doubt, both persistent and uncontroversially proven to have
had a point.
Between the beginning of the 18th century and the end of the 19th
century, many controversies arose around different mathematical
“results” concerning functions. Some of the controversial results were
rather technical, but they included the following two simple claims:24
1.Every function is continuous, except possibly at a finite number
of points.
2.Every continuous function is differentiable except possibly at a
finite number of points (see Hawkins 1975, 43–44).
Those claims were disputed because mathematicians were seemingly
“discovering” some “objects” whose existence appeared inconsistent with
their truth. In 1826, Abel, for example, showed that a certain function
defined as a convergent series of continuous functions is discontinuous
in an infinite number of points, apparently falsifying (1).25 In 1829, Dirichlet discovered the
eponymous “monster” function, which seemed like a function continuous
nowhere and thus to falsify (1).26 In 1872, finally, Weirstrass
introduced his own monster, which seemed to be a function that is
continuous everywhere but nowhere-differentiable and to falsify (2).27
These disputes involved earnest and rational thinkers; indeed, some
of the greatest mathematicians of the epoch ranged themselves on both
sides of the debate. Yet, the disputes concerning (1-2) were persistent
and were not clearly settled until the second decade of the 20th century
and the acceptance of modern set theory. The question arises as to how
(1-2)
could be maintained by many thinkers of quality despite the above
counterexamples. It would appear that some proponents of the
controversial statements denied that the alleged counterexamples were
significant exceptions to the general rule. Others denied that they were
genuine functions or even that they existed at all.
5.1 Was the Functions Controversy
Verbal?
It is tempting to make the charge that the Functions disputes were at
bottom merely verbal. Indeed, not all disputants
understood the term “function” in the same way. Neither did they all
define it with an equal degree of rigor and precision. Reviewing the
best textbooks in analysis, Hankel noticed in 1870 that among them, “one
[text] defines function in the Eulerian manner; the other that y should
change with x according to a rule, without explaining this mysterious
concept; the third defines them as Dirichlet; the fourth does not define
them at all; but everyone draws from them conclusions that are not
contained therein” (Kleiner 1989, 293).
There are, however, decisive reasons to think that even if the
mathematicians’ understanding of functions and their standards of rigor
differed quite significantly, this was not the cause of their disputes.
If their dispute had been merely verbal, (i) it
would have been defused by the introduction of new undisputed names to
refer to different kinds of functions, and (ii) its solution could only
have brought about a terminological advance, as opposed to a
substantial, genuinely mathematical progress. Neither of these was the
case in the event.28 By 1870, it was already clear to
many that one could distinguish between the “algebraic” functions, which
are defined by an “analytic expression” (i.e., algebraic formula), the
“geometric” functions (i.e., whose curve can be drawn freehand), and the
“logical” functions (i.e., arbitrary correspondences between two sets of
values). Indeed, those who introduced this revisionary and more
encompassing logical definition of function still wondered whether all
“logical functions” really existed, and if they did, whether they really
were functions. Thus Lakatos (1976, 151) points out that
according to Dirichlet himself, the “monster” he had discovered was “an
example not of an ‘ordinary’ real function, but of a function which does
not really deserve the name.” As late as 1904, Poincaré distinguished
between logical functions and analytic functions (locally expandable in
power series) and suggested that the former were not legitimate in
mathematics (see
Poincaré 1952, 125).29 Even more strikingly,
in 1905 Lebesgue, whose works permitted the generalization of the theory
of integration to some “monstrous” logical functions, still argued that
“true” functions are analytically representable (i.e.,
representable by an algebraic formula) (Lebesgue 1905, 139). Hermite
essentially shared this sentiment concerning “this lamentable evil of
functions without derivatives” (for Hermite’s view, see Kleiner 1989,
294).
Moreover, the lack of rigor and precision found in many of the
mathematicians’ definitions did not result from inattention or neglect.
Hence, the disagreement could not have been solved simply by
substituting more precise definitions for the imprecise ones. Many
mathematicians at that time explicitly rejected our modern standards of
rigor. It was common, for instance, to regard theorems as rules and
mathematical predicates as not in need of a precise formal definition
(see
especially Richards 2006, 700–713; and Lakatos 1976, 24). This
seems also to have been the conception of Euler himself (Youschkevitch 1976,
67). Rigor and precision could only develop, it was thought, at
the cost of fruitfulness. As Maloney (2008) puts it, Lebesgue, for
one, “[saw] the more precise and general definition of function, which
we essentially use today, as a frivolity at best and a liability at
worst.”
Ultimately, the solution to these disputes did not stem from
terminological advance, but from a substantial mathematical progress.
Modern set theory and distribution theory were developed in response to
such controversies. These controversies were laid to rest eventually,
but not before the emerging new theories had shown their credentials and
become entrenched in mathematical practice.
5.2 Was the Functions Controversy
Empty, Relativist or Inscrutable?
As we explained, the Functions Controversy was not verbal. It did not hinge on the fact that some
mathematicians, but not others, used a definition of functions, or true
functions, that excluded the “monsters.” Rather, it rested on the fact
that participants in these debates disagreed on which definition was the
best and ought to have been used. At this point, it might be suggested
that the dispute was perhaps empty or relativist. There is, however, a straightforward
argument to the effect that the dispute was neither empty nor relativist. If it
had been empty or relativist, it could not have been settled, and we
could not be said to know that (1-2) are in fact false. The same argument,
it should be noted, ipso facto shows that the dispute was not
inscrutable either.
Before moving forward, it is worth pausing on the decisive claim that
the Functions controversy has been settled and has, accordingly, a
point. We believe that in the present state of mathematics, this claim
is uncontroversial. We also believe that it is (almost) uncontroversial
that settling this dispute that way constituted a mathematical
progress (denying this would require developing a revisionary /
reactionary view of function that has no serious advocate today). What
is less clear and will be important later is the normative status of
this resolution, this progress, and the point of the dispute. A radical
conventionalist might argue that the Functions controversy was solved by
the mere acceptance of a stipulation (to the effect that functions are
logical functions) rather than by the discovery of a fact. He will
probably concede that this resolution constituted a progress, but only
because this stipulation was useful for us (and more useful than other
conflicting ones) and insist that we only have practical reasons to
consider (1) and (2) as true, not theoretical ones, and that the point of
the Functions Controversy was somehow insubstantial or superficial. On
the opposite side, Platonists, Kantians, Intuitionists, and even,
arguably, Poincaré-style conventionalists will consider that
mathematical truths do not depend on mere stipulations but on the
structure of the world or of our minds, that mathematical progress is
genuinely theoretical and substantial rather than merely pragmatic, and
that the point of the Fucntions Controversy was thus deep or
substantial. Let us call the first view of mathematical progress
deflationist. We do not need to take a stand on this deflationism
vs. non-deflationism debate here. What is important, however, is that
non-deflationism is very plausible and clearly the majority view. Many
philosophers, attracted by the claim that progress in philosophy is
impossible, scarce, or at best pragmatic—and that the point of
persistent disputes in philosophy is at best superficial—would be
tempted to grant that mathematical progress is common and usually deep
and theoretical.
5.3 The Point of the Functions
Controversy
If the Functions Controversy was neither verbal nor empty, and by
the same token, neither relativist nor inscrutable, it follows that it must have had a
point. What, then, was its point? One thing that our discussion suggests
already is that this controversy did not concern the properties of
something (namely, functions), of which the participants had a
common subjective understanding. Neither did it concern the
best way to articulate such a common understanding. There was no such
common understanding. Rather, disputants understood functions quite
differently, and they accordingly defined them quite differently and
accepted conflicting clusters of analytic claims about them. And their
dispute was (implicitly) about the best among their rival
understandings. Some mathematicians thought that the best understanding
was the algebraic or geometric one, and they assessed under its light
all claims about functions. Others favored the logical construal, and
these latter ended up on the right side of the debate, correctly denying
(1-2). Granting that one’s understanding of something is
reflected in the analytic claims one is disposed to accept concerning
that thing, we might say that the point of the Functions Controversy was
not analytic but rather meta-analytic. The fact that the
Functions Controversy was not verbal shows that
a dispute whose parties appeal to very different
understandings of the object at issue need not be verbal, provided that it is meta-analytic.
This is not a trivial conclusion. It might even seem problematic. On
the standard, neo-Fregean views of concepts (viz., ways of understanding
something that determine the reference to that thing in context),
different understandings imply different concepts, and if the parties disagree because they use (or
preferentially use) different concepts, it seems that their dispute must
be verbal after all. Fortunately, recent work in
philosophy of language and metaphilosophy focused on related phenomena
provides interesting ways out of this problem.
The first line of research in philosophy of language puts forward
“relationnist” or neo-Gricean semantics that canvass the possibility of
successful communication between two subjects that do not share the same
concepts.30 More germanely still, the second
line of research in metaphilosophy explicitly argues that what we call
meta-analytic disputes are not verbal. Some
philosophers working in the rapidly developing fields of metalinguistic
negotiations, conceptual ethics, and conceptual engineering understand
meta-analytic disputes as meta-conceptual, but argue that the concepts
involved, even if different, still share a common feature which prevents
the dispute from lapsing into the verbal. For
instance, they are said to be about the same “topic” (Cappelen 2018,
102–103), or are said to play the same role (Thomasson 2020).
Others claim that meta-analytic disputes need not be verbal because the disputants share a similar
meta-analytic aim. For instance, Belleri (forthcoming) writes of
a “semantically progressive inquiry” and asserts that the unity of
inquiry is at the bottom teleological. Yet others invoke externalist
views of concepts to argue that even though disputants understand the
object at issue in inconsistent ways, they might still share the same
concepts (Schroeter
and Schroeter 2014, 2016). Notably, Ball (2020) has argued that one should
construe what we have called meta-analytic disputes as metasemantic
disputes, that is, as disputes about the way one should “fix the
meaning of words as we have used them before.” In this article, we
remain neutral on the best view of concepts and meta-analytic
disputes.31 We observe, however, that there are
many ways to do justice to the non-verbal
character of such disputes.
5.4 The Functions Controversy and
the Pessimistic Challenge
We say that a dispute is meta-analytic when it bears on the
choice of the best way, among quite different candidates, to understand
something, rather than on the attribution of properties to something the
disputants understand in the same way, or on the best way to articulate
their shared understanding of it.
Interestingly, the meta-analytic reading of the Functions Controversy
allows us to provide a simple answer to the pessimistic challenge.
Take the competence problem first. According to the proposed
interpretation of the dispute, what prevented disputants from agreeing
was that they did not all understand (and hence define) functions in the
same way. More deeply, they disagreed about which understanding was the
best. But how, one might ask, could they disagree about that if they
were all competent enough to find out which understanding is the best,
and time cancelled the “usual suspects” for performance errors?
The comparative quality of competing understandings in pure
mathematics and elsewhere depends, importantly, on their consistency and
relative fruitfulness. It depends, more broadly, on their inferential
profiles, that is, on all the inferences one can draw by their means.
For finite minds like ours, however, evaluating such an inferential
profile is not instantaneous. Each inference takes a very small amount
of time to assess, but the number of inferences that need to be assessed
is virtually infinite. Assessing the inferential profile is thus an
open-ended process, that is, a process to which we cannot
assign an a priori upper bound in time, be it in terms of years, or even
centuries. Moreover, this process may prove surprising, as apparently
consistent understandings may sometimes prove inconsistent (think of the
naive understanding of sets, for a classical example), and apparently
useless re-construals may sometimes prove fruitful. This means that
assessing the relative merits of different ways to understand an object
will not only be an open-ended process, but also a
non-monotonic one: a process that may lead from a time when we
have most reason to favour one understanding \(U_{1}\) over the other one, \(U_{2}\), to a time when we have most reason
to favour \(U_{2}\) over \(U_{1}\).
For example, Poincaré, Lebesgue and Borel did not know, and they
arguably could not have known without years of inquiries and intricate
discussions with peers, that the logical understanding of a function
would find its place in an important and consistent mathematical theory
(set theory), that classical analysis would easily accommodate it, and
that it would prove extremely fruitful in many fields (the popular
Fractal theory is precisely a theory of “monstrous,” supposedly merely
logical, functions) and help provide many mathematical insights.32 It is in fact arguable that they
had good reason, at the very beginning of the 20th century, to dismiss
merely logical functions as useless curiosities.33
The open-ended character of the process of assessing competing
understandings successfully explains why it took mathematicians so long
to answer the questions surrounding (1-2), and consequently
to find out which understanding of “function” was the best. Conjoined
with the non-monotonic character of such a process, it furthermore
explains how such persistent questions gave rise to persistent
disputes. Each time a new aspect of the inferential profile was
discovered, its assessment necessarily took some time, allowing for the
emergence of dissenting views on the questions under scrutiny. In
general, as time passes, new results are made public, cognitive biases
and performance errors are removed through fruitful dialogues and
debates, and experts become able to fully grasp them. But by the time
this process reaches completion, new aspects of the competing
inferential profiles may have been discovered, whose assessment may once
again give rise to dissenting views through additional performance
errors, cognitive biases, or simply ordinary delays and difficulties in
communication. If assessing the comparative merits of two understandings
were a monotonic process, it could be argued that disputants should have
agreed sooner or later, owing to the gradual cancellation of
communicative difficulties, biases, and performance errors. Arguably,
they should have inferred, by monotonicity, that the dispute was settled
once and for all. Nevertheless, as we explained above, the comparative
assessment of two understandings is far from monotonic.
We pointed out at the outset that there is nothing mysterious in a
dispute that lasts for a very long time if new relevant empirical
evidence arises through continuous discovery. We are now able to make
this thought more precise. There is no mystery because the process of
assessing a growing body of empirical evidence is open-ended, if the
body of evidence grows, and non-monotonic. The Functions Controversy
persisted because it is a special kind of rational, non-empirical
evidence whose assessment is both open-ended and non-monotonic, similar,
in that respect, to the assessment of a growing body of empirical
evidence, and unlike the assessment of trivial analytic evidence. The
relevant a priori evidence was, in a sense, accessible all
along to all parties, granted sufficient
rationality. Being, however, open-ended and non-monotonic, its
assessment took a very long time.
Pessimists grant—or should grant—that new empirical evidence may fuel
ongoing debates in such a way that thinkers continue to disagree over
the same issue for decades or even centuries. We suggest that their
outright rejection of persistent disputes, in which by our definition
the empirical evidence is fixed, reveals an unjustified refusal to
acknowledge the existence of a type of evidence that is akin to
empirical evidence in that its assessment is open-ended and
non-monotonic, but that is, like trivial analytic evidence, a priori.
This evidence concerns in particular the assessment of different
understandings, which is open-ended, non-monotonic, and sometimes a
priori. It is meta-analytic.
The meta-analytic reading of the Functions Controversy thus answers
the competence problem. It also explains why disputants could disagree
on an a priori claim. Thus, it can solve the problem of apt a priori
disagreements. Even though the participants in the dispute
preferentially resorted to different understandings of the concept of a
function, we have seen that they were not talking past each other, and
that their disputes were not verbal because they
were meta-analytic. The fact that in a meta-analytic dispute, two parties can without misunderstanding
understand a disputed sentence in a radically different manner, should
already dispel the suspicion associated with certain views of the a
priori and the analytic, that any apt a priori disagreement must be verbal. The fact that a priori meta-analytic
disputes can be solved shows that apt a priori disagreement need not
imply that the disputes are either empty or relativist. More broadly, the meta-analytic reading
of the Functions Controversy implies that there are some a priori claims
that can only be known and understood by rational subjects’ appeal to
the best kind of understanding of the subject matter. So, for example,
the statement to the effect that “monster functions are genuine
functions” can only be known to be true by a subject who understands
functions in the right way. While a subject interpreting it in the
correct manner will endorse it, one who interprets it in another way is
likely to deny it, even though she understands it, hence to fail to know
that she does not know that monster functions are true functions.
This explains why, despite lively exchanges, some rational subjects
might fail to assent to a given a priori truth or even might dissent
from it, unknowingly failing to know that it is true. We have called
deceptive a priori truths truths on which rational subjects can
aptly disagree, and that they can, accordingly, wrongly believe to be
false, not knowing that they do not know them. On the meta-analytic
reading, the existence of deceptive a priori truths is not
mysterious. It does not require us to posit unusual or non-standard
analytic truths or a puzzling form of synthetic a priori.
Rather, it stems from the fact that different subjects associate
different understandings, and so different analytic truths, with a given
term, even though they both understand the term and therefore don’t
misunderstand each other or talk past each other.34
6 The Point of Persistent
Disputes
The Functions Controversy allows us to draw the following
conclusions: First, the fact that a dispute is persistent, or even
persistent and virtuous, does not entail that it is pointless. Second, a
good explanation as to why some disputes persist is that they are
meta-analytic and that meta-analytic evaluations, being open-ended and
non-monotonic, can take decades or even centuries. In order to find the
best understanding of a term, one might need to assess the full
inferential profile of the latter, which requires much time and can
always prove surprising. Finally, and given the plausibility of the
non-deflationary view of mathematical progress, the point of persistent
meta-analytic disputes can arguably be deep, substantial than merely
pragmatic.
The mere fact that a dispute is meta-analytic, as the example of the
Functions Controversy shows, does not entail that it is pointless. The
same could be said about the fact that the dispute is a priori. Even if
virtuous persistent disputes become a priori, that does not make them
pointless, because some evaluative claims about the comparative quality
of different understandings are a priori, yet can yield persistent
disputes that have a point.35
When the Pessimist proposed an abductive argument to the effect that
all persistent disputes are pointless, she may well have been right to
suppose that the disagreement factors in the epistemic profile of a
dispute (to recall, asymmetries in rationality, in the access to the
empirical evidence, and vicious epistemic circles) cannot explain its
persistence. The Pessimist was wrong, however, to draw the conclusion
that the best explanation of the persistence of a dispute is always that
it is pointless. In some cases, the best explanation is that the dispute
is meta-analytic and that meta-analytic disputes can involve the
open-ended and non-monotonic assessment of priori evidence. In such
cases, a persistent dispute need not be pointless. The competence
challenge is only challenging for someone who neglects, among the
disagreement factors, the difficulty of meta-analytic evaluations.
For all we know, there might be persistent disputes that are not
pointless, even though they are not meta-analytic. Yet we would like to
suggest that our diagnosis is quite general, and that many persistent
disputes in philosophy, in the sciences and in public life (i) are
meta-analytic and a priori (ii) persist precisely for this reason (iii)
crucially, are not necessarily pointless.
7 Meta-analytic Disputes,
Metalinguistic Negotiations, and Deep Disagreements
The view that many persistent disputes are meta-analytic disputes (as
we have called them) is not entirely new. Arguably, it has been held
under various guises by many philosophers, in relation to certain
scientific and philosophical persistent disputes. Carnap’s argument
against traditional ontology, for example, relied on the thesis that
disputes over meta-analytic questions (which he dubbed “external
questions”) are empty, or perhaps relativist (see fn. 5). The
view that persistent disputes are meta-analytic may well be at the root
of Gallie’s (1956) influential take on
“essentially contested concepts.” It may also be said to inform
Williams’ (2011,
vii–x) analysis of ethical disputes and, arguably, Kuhn’s (2012) understanding
of (the disputes surrounding) scientific revolutions.
More recently, Sider
(2009) has construed metaphysical disputes as disputes over the
best understanding of quantifiers (and the best quantifier concepts).
Many works in the fields of metalinguistic negotiations, conceptual
ethics, and the conceptual engineering literature have argued in a
similar vein that philosophical disputes are often metaconceptual (and
hence meta-analytic) disputes (Plunkett
2015; Burgess and Plunkett 2013; Cappelen 2018).
Likewise, Fogelin
(1985) noticed that many disputes are “deep” in the sense that
they stem from “a clash in underlying principles,” can accordingly
persist even though “the parties [are] unbiased, free of prejudice,
consistent, coherent, precise and rigorous” and “by their nature, are
not subject to rational resolution.” Godden and Brenner (2010) and
Shields (2021)
have all argued that deep disagreements are in fact meta-conceptual.
Our view that some meta-analytic disputes are both substantive and
scrutable and can persist without being pointless is much less
widespread, however. Indeed, all these authors, except the most recent
(e.g., Sider, Plunkett, Sundell, Burgess, Capellen, Shields (2021)),
seem to believe that meta-analytic or “metaconceptual” questions are
pointless. To our knowledge, even the latter do not put forward, as we
do, an explicit argument to the effect that such disputes can be
persistent and still have a point.36
More importantly, all of them seem to hold that the point of a
meta-conceptual dispute is always somehow pragmatic rather than deep and
substantial.37 The plausibility of the
non-deflationist view of mathematics strongly suggests that they are
wrong.
It is also worth noting that we have hinted at an argument for the
pervasive character of meta-analytic disputes just above, but that this
argument—call it the pervasiveness argument—is quite different from
those typically proposed in the metalinguistic and conceptual ethics
literature. First, in this literature, meta-analytic disputes are always
construed as metaconceptual or metalinguistic. We saw that there are
other construals of meta-analytic disputes. Second, the most thorough
arguments for the pervasive character of metaconceptual and
metalingustic disputes essentially rely on the linguistic data
surrounding some (potentially pointless) ordinary as well as
philosophical disputes. Plunkett’s (2015) important argument in this
vein is a case in point, insofar as it is a linguistic argument applied
to metaphilosophical questions. Roughly, his argument is that:
Some linguistic data suggest that a given exchange is a dispute
whose parties really disagree (i.e., they do not
misunderstand each other), but mean different things by the disputed
sentence.
The claim that their dispute is a metalinguistic negotiation can
explain these data, and it can explain them more simply than the claim
that the dispute is relativist or empty, which relies on complex non-standard
semantic frameworks (such as recent brands of expressivism or
relativism) (2015,
848–849).
Our argument relies partly on linguistic data as well, to wit, the
data surrounding the Functions Controversy. It relies mostly, however,
on epistemological and historical considerations to the effect that:
Some persistent meta-analytic disputes have proved to have a
point (the Functions Controversy).
The meta-analytic reading of a persistent virtuous dispute allows
us to defuse the best arguments for the charge that it is pointless, in
answer to the pessimistic challenge.
Accordingly, the ground for ruling out the rival relativist or expressivist analyses is not the
greater complexity, but the implication of pointlessness carried by
these alternative interpretations. One might see our pervasiveness
argument as contributing to the metalinguistic negotiation literature by
providing an additional, optimistic reason to believe that many
scientific and philosophical disputes are implicitly meta-analytic (and
thus maybe metalinguistic and metaconceptual) because they persist and
have a point. And of course, our main argument strengthens the interest
of such disputes, as it shows that they can have a point even though
they are persistent.
8 Conclusion
In this article, we examined and rejected the widespread imputation
that persistent disputes are pointless. Thus, we characterized pointless
disputes, put forward a typology, and reconstructed the strongest
pessimistic argument against the claim that persistent disputes might
have a point. To defuse the pessimistic argument, we proposed a
meta-analytic reading of a concrete example: the illustrious “Functions”
controversy. In general, when a dispute is meta-analytic, disputants
disagree about which understanding or set of analytical truths among
different candidates is the best one. The epistemic difficulty of
settling the disagreement at this level is what renders their dispute
persistent. Significantly, however, it does not render it pointless, as
this collective task is achievable in principle.
If this is true, then one should not have unnecessarily sanguine
expectations of the time it takes to settle such a dispute. To
paraphrase Hegel, who might here be classified as one of the greatest
optimists in the history of philosophy, one should trust the “power of
the negative,” for, in some instances, the very negativity of a
sustained disagreement may strengthen the natural power of reason.
References
Alston, William P. 1991. Perceiving God. The Epistemology of Religious
Experience. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.
Alston, William P. 2005. Beyond “Justification”: Dimensions of
Epistemic Evaluation. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University
Press, doi:10.7591/9781501720574.
Ball, Derek. 2020. “Revisionary Analysis without Meaning Change (Or, Could
Women Be Analytically Oppressed?).” in Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics,
pp. 35–58. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780198801856.003.0002.
Basham, Lee. 2001. “Living with the Conspiracy.”Philosophical Forum (Boston) 32(3): 265–280, doi:10.1111/0031-806X.00065.
Bayne, Tim[othy John]. 2007. “Hypnosis and the Unity of Consciousness.”
in Hypnosis and Conscious States. The Cognitive
Neuroscience Perspective, edited by Graham A. Jamieson, pp. 93–109. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780198569794.003.0006.
Bayne, Tim[othy John] and Pacherie, Elisabeth. 2004. “Experience, Belief, and the Interpretive
Fold.”Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology
11(1): 81–86, doi:10.1353/ppp.2004.0034.
Belleri, Delia. forthcoming. “Downplaying the Change of Subject Objection to Conceptual
Engineering.”Inquiry, doi:10.1080/0020174X.2021.1908161.
Bennett, Karen. 2009. “Composition, Colocation, and Metaontology.”
in Metametaphysics. New Essays on the
Foundations of Ontology, edited by David J. Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman, pp. 38–76. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780199546046.003.0002.
Block, Ned. 2005. “Two Neural Correlates of Consciousness.”Trends in Cognitive Science 9(2): 46–52. Reprinted in
Block (2007a,
342–361), doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.12.006.
Block, Ned. 2007b. “Consciousness, Accessibility, and the Mesh Between
Psychology and Neuroscience.”Behavioral and Brain
Sciences 30: 481–548, doi:10.1017/s0140525x07002786.
Buchanan, Ray. 2014. “Reference, Understanding, and
Communication.”Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 92(1): 55–70, doi:10.1080/00048402.2013.788526.
Cappelen, Herman. 2018. Fixing Language. An Essay on Conceptual
Engineering. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780198814719.001.0001.
Carnap, Rudolf. 1931.
“Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische
Analyse der Sprache.”Erkenntnis 2: 219–241.
Reprinted and translated in Ayer (1959, 60–81), doi:10.1007/bf02028153.
Carnap, Rudolf. 1950. “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.”Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4(11): 20–40.
Reprinted in Carnap (1956, 205–221).
Castelvecchi, Davide. 2020.
“Mathematical Proof That Rocked Number Theory Will Be
Published.”Nature 580(7802), doi:10.1038/d41586-020-00998-2.
Chalmers, David J. 2011.
“Verbal Disputes.”The Philosophical
Review 120(4): 515–566, doi:10.1215/00318108-1334478.
Christensen, David. 2007. “Epistemology of Disagreement: The Good
News.”The Philosophical Review 116(2): 187–217,
doi:10.1215/00318108-2006-035.
Dehaene, Stanislaus and Naccache, Lionel. 2001. “Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of Consciousness: Basic
Evidence and a Workspace Framework.”Cognition
79: 1–37, doi:10.1016/s0010-0277(00)00123-2.
Feldman, Richard H. 2003.
Epistemology. Foundations of
Philosophy Series. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall,
Inc.
Feldman, Richard H. 2006. “Epistemological Puzzles about
Disagreement.” in Epistemology
Futures, edited by Stephen Cade Hetherington, pp. 216–236. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780199273317.003.0013.
Feltz, Adam and Cokely, Edward T. 2013. “Predicting
Philosophical Disagreement.”Philosophy Compass
8(10): 978–989, doi:10.1111/phc3.12076.
Frege, Gottlob. 1956. “The
Thought: A Logical Inquiry.”Mind 65(259):
289–311. Translation of Frege (1918) by Anthony Quinton and
Marcelle Quinton, doi:10.1093/mind/65.1.289.
Gallie, Walter Bryce. 1956.
“Essentially Contested Concepts.”Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56: 167–198, doi:10.1093/aristotelian/56.1.167.
Godden, David M. and Brenner, William H. 2010. “Wittgenstein and the Logic of Deep Disagreement
.”Cogency. Journal of Reasoning and
Argumentation 2(2): 41–80.
Gottlieb, Joseph. 2018. “Verbal Disputes in the Theory of
Consciousness.”Ergo 5(12): 319–347, doi:10.3998/ergo.12405314.0005.012.
Gray, Jeremy J. 1991. “Did
Poincaré Say ‘Set Theory Is a
Disease’?”The Mathematical Intelligencer
13(1): 19–22, doi:10.1007/BF03024067.
Hawkins, Thomas. 1975. Lebesgue’s Theory of Integration: Its Origins and
Development. New York: Chelsea Publishing Company.
Hawthorne, John. 2009. “Superficialism in Ontology.” in Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of
Ontology, edited by David J. Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman, pp. 213–230. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780199546046.003.0007.
Hirsch, Eli. 2009. “Ontology and Alternative Languages.” in
Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations
of Ontology, edited by David J. Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman, pp. 231–259. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780199546046.003.0008.
Hirsch, Eli. 2016. “Three Degrees of Carnapian Tolerance.” in
Ontology after Carnap, edited by
Stephan Blatti and Sandra Lapointe, pp. 105–121. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199661985.003.0006.
Hohwy, Jakob and Rosenberg, Raben. 2005. “Unusual Experiences, Reality Testing, and Delusions of
Alien Control.”Mind and Language 20(2): 141–162,
doi:10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00280.x.
vanInwagen, Peter. 2017. Thinking about Free Will. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/9781316711101.
James, William. 1902. The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human
Nature. London: Longmans, Green & Co.
Kahneman, Daniel, Slovic, Paul and Tversky, Amos, eds. 1982. Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and
Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511809477.
Kelly, Thomas. 2005. “The Epistemic Significance of
Disagreement.” in Oxford Studies
in Epistemology, volume I, edited by Tamar Szabó Gendler and John Hawthorne, pp. 167–196. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780199285891.003.0007.
Kelly, Thomas. 2010. “Peer Disagreement and Higher-Order
Evidence.” in Disagreement, edited
by Richard H. Feldman and Ted A. Warfield, pp. 111–174. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199226078.003.0007.
Kleiner, Israel. 1989. “Evolution of the Function Concept: A Brief
Survey.”The College Mathematics Journal 20(4):
282–300, doi:10.2307/2686848.
Kouider, Sid, Dehaene, Stanislaus, Jobert, Antoinette and Le Bihan, Denis. 2007. “Cerebral Bases of Subliminal and Supraliminal Priming
During Reading.”Cerebral Cortex 17(9):
2019–2029, doi:10.1093/cercor/bhl110.
Kouider, Sid, Sackur, Jérôme and Gardelle, Vincent de. 2012. “Do we Still Need Phenomenal Consciousness? Comment on
Block
(2011).”Trends in Cognitive Science
16(3): 140–141, doi:10.1016/j.tics.2012.01.003.
Kriegel, Uriah. 2013. “The Epistemological Challenge of Revisionary
Metaphysics.”Philosophers’ Imprint 13(12).
Kuhn, Thomas S. 2012. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press. 50th Anniversary
Edition, with an introductory essay by Ian Hacking; original
publication: Kuhn
(1962a).
Lakatos, Imre. 1976. Proofs and Refutations: The Logic of Mathematical
Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Republished as Lakatos (2015).
Lamme, V. A. F. 2004. “Separate Neural Definitions of Visual Consciousness and
Visual Attention; a Case for Phenomenal Awareness.”Neural Networks 17(5–6): 861–872, doi:10.1016/j.neunet.2004.02.005.
LaPorte, Joseph. 2004. Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change. Cambrige Studies in Philosophy and Biology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511527319.
Lebesgue, Henri. 1905.
“Recherches sur la convergence des séries de
Fourier.”Mathematische Annalen 61(2): 251–280,
doi:10.1007/BF01457565.
Levy, Neil. 2019. “Due Deference to Denialism: Explaining Ordinary People’s
Rejection of Established Scientific Findings.”Synthese 196(1): 313–327, doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1477-x.
Locke, John. 1975. An Essay concerning Human Understanding.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited with a foreword by Peter
H. Nidditch, doi:10.1093/actrade/9780198243861.book.1.
MacFarlane, John. 2014. Assessment Sensitivity: Relative Truth and Its
Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682751.001.0001.
Naccache, Lionel. 2005.
“Visual Phenomenal Consciousness: A Neurological Guided Tour
.”Progress in Brain Research 150: 185–195,
doi:10.1016/S0079-6123(05)50013-X.
Nguyen, C. Thi. 2020. “Echo Chambers and Epistemic Bubbles.”Episteme 17(2): 141–161, doi:10.1017/epi.2018.32.
Plantinga, Alvin. 2000.
Warranted Christian Belief. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/0195131932.001.0001.
Plunkett, David. 2015. “Which Concepts should we Use? Metalinguistic Negotiations
and the Methodology of Philosophy.”Inquiry
58(7–8): 828–874, doi:10.1080/0020174X.2015.1080184.
Plunkett, David and Sundell, Timothy. 2013. “Disagreement and the Semantics of Normative and
Evaluative Terms.”Philosophers’ Imprint 13(23).
Poincaré, Henri. 1899.
“L’œuvre mathématique de
Weierstrass.”Acta Mathematica 22(1): 1–18.
Poincaré, Henri. 1952. Science and Method. Mineola, New York: Dover
Publications.
Pryor, James. 2016. “Mental
Graphs.”The Review of Philosophy and Psychology
7(2): 309–341, doi:10.1007/s13164-015-0280-1.
Rescher, Nicholas. 1985. The Strife of Systems. An Essay on the Grounds and
Implications of Philosophical Diversity. Pittsburgh,
Pennsylvania: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Richards, Joan L. 2006. “Historical Mathematics in the French Eighteenth
Century.”Isis 97(4): 700–713, doi:10.1086/509951.
Rosenthal, David M. 2002. “How Many Kinds of Consciousness?”Consciousness and Cognition 11(4): 653–665, doi:10.1016/S1053-8100(02)00017-X.
Schellenberg, J. L. 2007. The Wisdom to Doubt. A Justification of Religious
Skepticism. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press,
doi:10.7591/9780801462399.
Schlick, Moritz. 1930. “Die
Wende der Philosophie.”Erkenntnis 1(1): 4–11.
Reprinted as “The Turning Point in Philosophy” in
Ayer (1959,
53–59), doi:10.1007/bf00208605.
Schroeter, Laura and Schroeter, François. 2014.
“Normative Concepts: A Connectedness Model.”Philosophers’ Imprint 14(25).
Schroeter, Laura and Schroeter, François. 2016. “Semantic Deference versus Semantic
Coordination.”American Philosophical Quarterly
53(2): 193–210.
Sergent, Claire and Dehaene, Stanislaus. 2005. “Neural Processes Underlying Conscious Perception:
Experimental Findings and a Global Neuronal Workspace Framework
.”Journal of Physiology 98(4–6): 374–384, doi:10.1016/j.jphysparis.2005.09.006.
Shields, Matthew. 2021. “On the Pragmatics of Deep Disagreement.”Topoi 40(5): 999–1015, doi:10.1007/s11245-018-9602-0.
Sider, Theodore. 2009.
“Ontological Realism.” in Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of
Ontology, edited by David J. Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman, pp. 384–423. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780199546046.003.0013.
Sosa, Ernest. 2010. “The Epistemology of Disagreement.” in
Social Epistemology, edited by Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, and Duncan Pritchard, pp. 278–297. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199577477.003.0014.
Stoljar, Daniel. 2017. Philosophical Progress. In Defence of a Reasonable
Optimism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780198802099.001.0001.
Taschek, William W. 1995. “Belief, Substitution, and Logical
Structure.”Noûs 29(1): 71–95,
doi:10.2307/2215727.
Thomasson, Amie L. 2009. “Answerable and Unanswerable Questions.” in
Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations
of Ontology, edited by David J. Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman, pp. 444–471. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780199546046.003.0015.
Thomasson, Amie L. 2020. “A Pragmatic Method for Conceptual Ethics.”
in Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual
Ethics, pp. 435–458. Oxford: Oxford University Press, doi:10.1093/oso/9780198801856.003.0021.
Williams, Bernard Arthur Owen. 2011.
Ethics and the Limits of
Philosophy. London: Routledge. With a commentary on
the text by A.W. Moore and a foreword by Jonathan Lear; original
publication: Williams (1985), doi:10.4324/9780203828281.
Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/019925656X.001.0001.
Williamson, Timothy. 2007. The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford:
Blackwell Publishers. Second edition: Williamson (2021), doi:10.1002/9780470696675.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1929. “Some Remarks on Logical Form.”Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume
9: 162–171, doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/9.1.162.
Yablo, Stephen. 2009. “Must
Existence-Questions Have Answers?” in Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of
Ontology, edited by David J. Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman, pp. 507–526. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199266487.003.0013.
Youschkevitch, Adolph-Andrei Pavlovich.
1976. “The Concept of Function up to the
Middle of the 18th and the 19th Century.”Archive for
the History of the Exact Sciences 16(1): 37–85, doi:10.1007/BF00348305.
Zeki, Semir and Ffytche, Dominic H. 1998. “The Riddoch Syndrome: Insights in the Neurobiology of
Conscious Vision .”Brain: A Journal of Neurology
121(1): 25–45, doi:10.1093/brain/121.1.25.
Carnap, Rudolf. 1947. Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal
Logic. 1st ed. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago
Press. Second edition: Carnap (1956).
Carnap, Rudolf. 1956. Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal
Logic. 2nd ed. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago
Press. Enlarged edition of Carnap (1947).
Frege, Gottlob. 1918. “Der
Gedanke. Eine logische Untersuchung.”Beiträge zur Philosophie des Deutschen Idealismus
1: 58–77. Ed. by Arthur Hoffmann and Horst Engert; Erfurt: Verlag
der Keyserschen Buchhandlung, reprinted in Frege (1993).
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962a. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press. Separate book
publication of Kuhn
(1962b); second edition: Kuhn (1970).
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962b. “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.”International Encyclopedia of Unified Science 2(2).
Reprinted in Neurath, Carnap and Morris (1970,
53–272).
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd
ed. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press. Enlarged,
second edition of Kuhn
(1962a).
Lakatos, Imre. 2015. Proofs and Refutations: The Logic of Mathematical
Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Republication of Lakatos (1976), edited by John Worrall
and Elie Zahar, doi:10.1017/cbo9781316286425.
Neurath, Otto, Carnap, Rudolf and Morris, Charles W., eds. 1970. Foundations of the Unity of Science: Toward an
International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Volume II.
Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press.
Williams, Bernard Arthur Owen. 1985.
Ethics and the Limits of
Philosophy. London: Fontana Press.
Williamson, Timothy. 2021. The Philosophy of Philosophy. 2nd ed. The Blackwell / Brown Lectures in Philosophy.
Hoboken, New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell. First edition: Williamson
(2007), doi:10.1002/9781119616702.